比特派app下载安卓|solidarity

作者: 比特派app下载安卓
2024-03-09 21:01:42

SOLIDARITY中文(简体)翻译:剑桥词典

SOLIDARITY中文(简体)翻译:剑桥词典

词典

翻译

语法

同义词词典

+Plus

剑桥词典+Plus

Shop

剑桥词典+Plus

我的主页

+Plus 帮助

退出

剑桥词典+Plus

我的主页

+Plus 帮助

退出

登录

/

注册

中文 (简体)

查找

查找

英语-中文(简体)

solidarity 在英语-中文(简体)词典中的翻译

solidaritynoun [ U ] uk

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɒl.ɪˈdær.ə.ti/ us

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɑː.lɪˈder.ə.t̬i/

Add to word list

Add to word list

C1 agreement between and support for the members of a group, especially a political group

团结一致

The situation raises important questions about solidarity among member states of the UN.

当前形势对联合国成员国能否团结一致这一重要问题提出了质疑。

The purpose of the speech was to show solidarity with the country's leaders.

这场演讲的目的是为了表示与国家领导人团结一致。

(solidarity在剑桥英语-中文(简体)词典的翻译 © Cambridge University Press)

solidarity的例句

solidarity

The latter response is reinforced in us by our obligation to stand in solidarity with victims of wrongdoing against those who have wronged them.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

As the structural dimension of solidarity had not strengthened, it was not surprising that the third hypotheses also had to be rejected.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

In terms of solidarity, the free rider has two options.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

They then use this model in crafting their solidarity activities and in dispensing resources.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

The relationship will not always exclude maintenance of traditional clientelistic ties or ethnic solidarity.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

In reality, a great number of households depend on both a good monetary income and a functional solidarity system inside and outside the home.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

The motivation is more to do with protecting the inherited connection between social solidarity and national sovereignty.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

However, future studies offer the potential to compare the effects of, for example, civic duty, neighbourhood solidarity and close election messages.

来自 Cambridge English Corpus

示例中的观点不代表剑桥词典编辑、剑桥大学出版社和其许可证颁发者的观点。

C1

solidarity的翻译

中文(繁体)

團結一致…

查看更多内容

西班牙语

solidaridad…

查看更多内容

葡萄牙语

solidariedade…

查看更多内容

更多语言

in Marathi

土耳其语

法语

in Dutch

in Tamil

in Hindi

in Gujarati

丹麦语

in Swedish

马来语

德语

挪威语

in Urdu

in Ukrainian

俄语

in Telugu

in Bengali

捷克语

印尼语

泰语

越南语

波兰语

एकजूट, गटाच्या सदस्यांमधील करार आणि समर्थन, विशेषत: राजकीय गट…

查看更多内容

dayanışma, birlik, yekvücut olma…

查看更多内容

solidarité…

查看更多内容

solidariteit…

查看更多内容

ஒரு குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு, குறிப்பாக ஒரு அரசியல் குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு இடையே உடன்பாடு மற்றும் ஆதரவு…

查看更多内容

(प्रायः राजनीतिक) एकजुटता…

查看更多内容

એકતા, ઐક્ય…

查看更多内容

solidaritet…

查看更多内容

solidaritet, samhörighetskänsla…

查看更多内容

perpaduan…

查看更多内容

der Zusammenhalt…

查看更多内容

solidaritet, fellesskapsfølelse…

查看更多内容

یکجہتی, ہم آہنگی…

查看更多内容

солідарність, згуртованість…

查看更多内容

солидарность…

查看更多内容

సమూహానికి, ముఖ్యంగా రాజకీయ సమూహానికి చెందిన సభ్యుల మధ్య ఒప్పందం, ఒకరికొకరి మద్దతు…

查看更多内容

সংহতি…

查看更多内容

soudržnost…

查看更多内容

solidaritas…

查看更多内容

ความสามัคคี…

查看更多内容

tình đoàn kết…

查看更多内容

solidarność…

查看更多内容

需要一个翻译器吗?

获得快速、免费的翻译!

翻译器工具

solidarity的发音是什么?

在英语词典中查看 solidarity 的释义

浏览

solid

solid fuel

solid-state

solid-state drive

solidarity

solidification

solidify

solidity

solidly

“每日一词”

flexitarian

A flexitarian way of eating consists mainly of vegetarian food but with some meat.

关于这个

博客

Forget doing it or forget to do it? Avoiding common mistakes with verb patterns (2)

March 06, 2024

查看更多

新词

stochastic parrot

March 04, 2024

查看更多

已添加至 list

回到页面顶端

内容

英语-中文(简体)例句翻译

©剑桥大学出版社与评估2024

学习

学习

学习

新词

帮助

纸质书出版

Word of the Year 2021

Word of the Year 2022

Word of the Year 2023

开发

开发

开发

词典API

双击查看

搜索Widgets

执照数据

关于

关于

关于

无障碍阅读

剑桥英语教学

剑桥大学出版社与评估

授权管理

Cookies与隐私保护

语料库

使用条款

京ICP备14002226号-2

©剑桥大学出版社与评估2024

剑桥词典+Plus

我的主页

+Plus 帮助

退出

词典

定义

清晰解释自然的书面和口头英语

英语

学习词典

基础英式英语

基础美式英语

翻译

点击箭头改变翻译方向。

双语词典

英语-中文(简体)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

英语-中文(繁体)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

英语-荷兰语

荷兰语-英语

英语-法语

法语-英语

英语-德语

德语-英语

英语-印尼语

印尼语-英语

英语-意大利语

意大利语-英语

英语-日语

日语-英语

英语-挪威语

挪威语-英语

英语-波兰语

波兰语-英语

英语-葡萄牙语

葡萄牙语-英语

英语-西班牙语

西班牙语-英语

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

半双语词典

英语-阿拉伯语

英语-孟加拉语

英语-加泰罗尼亚语

英语-捷克语

英语-丹麦语

English–Gujarati

英语-印地语

英语-韩语

英语-马来语

英语-马拉地语

英语-俄语

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

英语-泰语

英语-土耳其语

英语-乌克兰语

English–Urdu

英语-越南语

翻译

语法

同义词词典

Pronunciation

剑桥词典+Plus

Shop

剑桥词典+Plus

我的主页

+Plus 帮助

退出

登录 /

注册

中文 (简体)  

Change

English (UK)

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

中文 (简体)

正體中文 (繁體)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

हिंदी

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

关注我们

选择一本词典

最近的词和建议

定义

清晰解释自然的书面和口头英语

英语

学习词典

基础英式英语

基础美式英语

语法与同义词词典

对自然书面和口头英语用法的解释

英语语法

同义词词典

Pronunciation

British and American pronunciations with audio

English Pronunciation

翻译

点击箭头改变翻译方向。

双语词典

英语-中文(简体)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

英语-中文(繁体)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

英语-荷兰语

荷兰语-英语

英语-法语

法语-英语

英语-德语

德语-英语

英语-印尼语

印尼语-英语

英语-意大利语

意大利语-英语

英语-日语

日语-英语

英语-挪威语

挪威语-英语

英语-波兰语

波兰语-英语

英语-葡萄牙语

葡萄牙语-英语

英语-西班牙语

西班牙语-英语

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

半双语词典

英语-阿拉伯语

英语-孟加拉语

英语-加泰罗尼亚语

英语-捷克语

英语-丹麦语

English–Gujarati

英语-印地语

英语-韩语

英语-马来语

英语-马拉地语

英语-俄语

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

英语-泰语

英语-土耳其语

英语-乌克兰语

English–Urdu

英语-越南语

词典+Plus

词汇表

选择语言

中文 (简体)  

English (UK)

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

正體中文 (繁體)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

हिंदी

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

内容

英语-中文(简体) 

 Noun

例句

Translations

语法

所有翻译

我的词汇表

把solidarity添加到下面的一个词汇表中,或者创建一个新词汇表。

更多词汇表

前往词汇表

对该例句有想法吗?

例句中的单词与输入词条不匹配。

该例句含有令人反感的内容。

取消

提交

例句中的单词与输入词条不匹配。

该例句含有令人反感的内容。

取消

提交

solidarity是什么意思_solidarity的翻译_音标_读音_用法_例句_爱词霸在线词典

darity是什么意思_solidarity的翻译_音标_读音_用法_例句_爱词霸在线词典首页翻译背单词写作校对词霸下载用户反馈专栏平台登录solidarity是什么意思_solidarity用英语怎么说_solidarity的翻译_solidarity翻译成_solidarity的中文意思_solidarity怎么读,solidarity的读音,solidarity的用法,solidarity的例句翻译人工翻译试试人工翻译翻译全文简明柯林斯牛津solidarityCET6/考研/GRE/TOEFL/IELTS英 [ˌsɒlɪˈdærəti]美 [ˌsɑːlɪˈdærəti]释义n.团结点击 人工翻译,了解更多 人工释义词态变化复数: solidarities;实用场景例句全部团结community solidarity社群团结牛津词典to express/show solidarity with sb表示 / 表明支持某人牛津词典Demonstrations were held as a gesture of solidarity with the hunger strikers.人们举行示威游行,以表示对绝食抗议者的支持。牛津词典Supporters want to march tomorrow to show solidarity with their leaders.为了显示和领袖的同心同德,支持者们希望明天举行游行。柯林斯高阶英语词典What is needed is mutual encouragement, solidarity, and practical organization.我们需要的是一个互勉 、 团结 、 实干的组织.期刊摘选Part of the General Programme of the draft Constitution dwells on Party solidarity and unity.在党章草案的总纲中有一部分是说明党的团结和统一的.期刊摘选The suicide bomber detonated his explosives at a Shi'ite rally expressing solidarity with the Palestinian people.自杀炸弹杀手在一个什叶派支持巴勒斯坦人的集会上引爆炸弹.期刊摘选We respect knowledge and personality cry up collective power, solidarity and cooperation all the more.我们尊重知识、尊重个性,更推崇集体力量 、 团结协作.期刊摘选Fourthly, the Shanghai Expo will promote confidence and solidarity in meeting global challenges.第四, 上海世博会将凝聚信心力量,团结应对挑战.期刊摘选The perennial conflict between national egoism and international solidarity becomes and more visible.国家利己主义和国际的团结之间的长期冲突变得越来越明显.期刊摘选The solidarity among China's various nationalities is as firm as a rock.中国各族人民之间的团结坚如磐石.《现代汉英综合大词典》Any political entity would invoke religious solidarity to muster its strength in numbers.政治组织更不惜利用宗教来招兵买马和团结人心.期刊摘选He therefore showed little interest in the gestures of active solidarity from Madrid.因此,他对于马德里的这副积极拉拢的姿态并不怎么感兴趣.辞典例句That is an uncomfortable reminder of the way group solidarity works in America.这对于在美国进行的种族团结而言,可不是一个令其愉快的消息.期刊摘选We will resolutely oppose any activity aimed at splitting the motherland or undermining ethnic solidarity.坚决反对分裂祖国和破坏民族团结的行为.期刊摘选The fourth is over how to reinforce solidarity.第四个选择是如何巩固团结.期刊摘选The ideas of communist solidarity and laying low to focus on modernization are becoming obsolete.共产主义团结以及不重视现代化的理念已经变得过时.期刊摘选Such a vision of the solidarity of life had never before come to Lily.这种人与人之间休戚相关的关系是丽莉以前从未体验过的.辞典例句In southern Europe, solidarity is measured in the billions sent by the EU to needy governments.南欧团结一致是用欧盟送给有需要的政府数十亿欧元来衡量的.期刊摘选In brotherly love there is the experience of union with all men , of human solidarity.手足之爱包括同所有人和睦相处, 团结一致.期刊摘选On our heads, and the certificate the basketball game last week, with all our solidarity disclosed.我们头顶上的这些奖状, 以及上个星期的篮球赛, 无不透漏着我们所有人团结的力量.期刊摘选They must preserve their solidarity.他们必须维护他们的团结.《简明英汉词典》Though the bloodiness of the earthquake, Chinese nationality show the huge solidarity.虽然这次残酷的残酷, 中华民族显示出了强大的团结.期刊摘选The great friendship and militant solidarity between the peoples of our two countries are unbreakable.我们两国人民的伟大友谊与战斗团结是坚不可摧的.《现代汉英综合大词典》Supporters want to march tomorrow to show solidarity with their leaders.为了显示和领袖的同心同德,支持者们希望明天举行游行。柯林斯例句Drivers honked their horns in solidarity with the peace marchers.司机按响汽车喇叭,支持反战示威游行者。柯林斯例句There was a degree of solidarity and sisterhood among the women.这些女人之间存在着一定程度的团结精神和姐妹情谊。柯林斯例句The bitter split which has developed within Solidarity is likely to harden further into separation.团结工会内部已产生的不愉快分歧可能会进一步演变为分裂。柯林斯例句收起实用场景例句真题例句全部六级考研Nick Perks, project director for Climate Solidarity, believes this sort of activity is where the future of environmental action lies.出自-2015年12月阅读原文A retired member of the Public and Commercial Services Union, she is setting up one of 1,100 action groups with the support of Climate Solidarity, a two-year environmental campaign aimed at trade unionists.出自-2015年12月阅读原文nick Perks, project director for Climate Solidarity, believes this sort of activity is where the future of environmental action lies.2015年12月六级真题(第二套)阅读 Section BDurkheim proposed that religious beliefs functioned to reinforce social solidarity.出自-2009年考研阅读原文收起真题例句英英释义Noun1. a union of interests or purposes or sympathies among members of a group收起英英释义词根词缀词根: solid表示"巩固,团结"adj.solid 固体的, 实心的solid巩固,团结→n.固体, 立体 adj.固体的, 实心的solidary 团结一致的,休戚相关的solid巩固,团结+ary表形容词→adj.团结一致的,休戚相关的n.solid 固体, 立体 solid巩固,团结→n.固体, 立体 adj.固体的, 实心的solidarity 团结solidary[adj.团结一致的,休戚相关的]+ity表名词→solidarity团结v.solidify [使]凝固,[使]团结, 巩固solid巩固,团结+ify表动词→v.[使]凝固,[使]团结, 巩固同义词n.稳固,坚定,可靠,能力,力量,完整,完全powerfirmnesswholenessentiretysoundnesstotalitycompletenessintegritystabilitytrustworthinessreliabilitystrengthn.赞同,协调,一致,共同关心,团体精神concordunionfeelingteamlike-mindednessconsensusinunanimitynumbersstrengthfellowshipaccordconcordancespiritaccordanceharmonyfellowconsentaneityonenessconcurrencesingle-mindednessunity行业词典医学互助对有限的卫生资源进行公平而合理的配置时的道德原则   释义词态变化实用场景例句真题例句英英释义词根词缀同义词行

SOLIDARITY中文(繁體)翻譯:劍橋詞典

SOLIDARITY中文(繁體)翻譯:劍橋詞典

詞典

翻譯

文法

同義詞詞典

+Plus

劍橋詞典+Plus

Shop

劍橋詞典+Plus

我的主頁

+Plus 幫助

退出

劍橋詞典+Plus

我的主頁

+Plus 幫助

退出

登錄

/

註冊

正體中文 (繁體)

查找

查找

英語-中文(繁體)

solidarity 在英語-中文(繁體)詞典中的翻譯

solidaritynoun [ U ] uk

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɒl.ɪˈdær.ə.ti/ us

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɑː.lɪˈder.ə.t̬i/

Add to word list

Add to word list

C1 agreement between and support for the members of a group, especially a political group

團結一致

The situation raises important questions about solidarity among member states of the UN.

當前形勢對聯合國成員國能否團結一致這一重要問題提出了質疑。

The purpose of the speech was to show solidarity with the country's leaders.

這場演講的目的是為了表示與國家領導人團結一致。

(solidarity在劍橋英語-中文(繁體)詞典的翻譯 © Cambridge University Press)

solidarity的例句

solidarity

A positive politeness strategy highlights involvement, solidarity, and common membership, which are the essence of intimacy.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

Prebendalism is essentially a system of shared identity and social solidarity expressing itself through a circuit which concentrates and redistributes income.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

They then use this model in crafting their solidarity activities and in dispensing resources.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

Religious solidarity and national identity are thus forced into exclusive paradigms, which do not recognise the different narratives within each ideology.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

As the structural dimension of solidarity had not strengthened, it was not surprising that the third hypotheses also had to be rejected.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

The relationship will not always exclude maintenance of traditional clientelistic ties or ethnic solidarity.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

The motivation is more to do with protecting the inherited connection between social solidarity and national sovereignty.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

Each individual is integrated into various networks, each of which entails solidarities and therefore corresponding pressures.

來自 Cambridge English Corpus

示例中的觀點不代表劍橋詞典編輯、劍橋大學出版社和其許可證頒發者的觀點。

C1

solidarity的翻譯

中文(簡體)

团结一致…

查看更多內容

西班牙語

solidaridad…

查看更多內容

葡萄牙語

solidariedade…

查看更多內容

更多語言

in Marathi

土耳其語

法語

in Dutch

in Tamil

in Hindi

in Gujarati

丹麥語

in Swedish

馬來西亞語

德語

挪威語

in Urdu

in Ukrainian

俄語

in Telugu

in Bengali

捷克語

印尼語

泰語

越南語

波蘭語

एकजूट, गटाच्या सदस्यांमधील करार आणि समर्थन, विशेषत: राजकीय गट…

查看更多內容

dayanışma, birlik, yekvücut olma…

查看更多內容

solidarité…

查看更多內容

solidariteit…

查看更多內容

ஒரு குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு, குறிப்பாக ஒரு அரசியல் குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு இடையே உடன்பாடு மற்றும் ஆதரவு…

查看更多內容

(प्रायः राजनीतिक) एकजुटता…

查看更多內容

એકતા, ઐક્ય…

查看更多內容

solidaritet…

查看更多內容

solidaritet, samhörighetskänsla…

查看更多內容

perpaduan…

查看更多內容

der Zusammenhalt…

查看更多內容

solidaritet, fellesskapsfølelse…

查看更多內容

یکجہتی, ہم آہنگی…

查看更多內容

солідарність, згуртованість…

查看更多內容

солидарность…

查看更多內容

సమూహానికి, ముఖ్యంగా రాజకీయ సమూహానికి చెందిన సభ్యుల మధ్య ఒప్పందం, ఒకరికొకరి మద్దతు…

查看更多內容

সংহতি…

查看更多內容

soudržnost…

查看更多內容

solidaritas…

查看更多內容

ความสามัคคี…

查看更多內容

tình đoàn kết…

查看更多內容

solidarność…

查看更多內容

需要一個翻譯器嗎?

獲得快速、免費的翻譯!

翻譯器工具

solidarity的發音是什麼?

在英語詞典中查看 solidarity 的釋義

瀏覽

solid

solid fuel

solid-state

solid-state drive

solidarity

solidification

solidify

solidity

solidly

「每日一詞」

flexitarian

A flexitarian way of eating consists mainly of vegetarian food but with some meat.

關於這個

部落格

Forget doing it or forget to do it? Avoiding common mistakes with verb patterns (2)

March 06, 2024

查看更多

新詞

stochastic parrot

March 04, 2024

查看更多

已添加至 list

回到頁面頂端

內容

英語-中文(繁體)例句翻譯

©劍橋大學出版社與評估2024

學習

學習

學習

新詞

幫助

紙本出版

Word of the Year 2021

Word of the Year 2022

Word of the Year 2023

開發

開發

開發

詞典API

連按兩下查看

搜尋Widgets

執照資料

關於

關於

關於

無障礙閱讀

劍橋英語教學

劍橋大學出版社與評估

授權管理

Cookies與隱私保護

語料庫

使用條款

京ICP备14002226号-2

©劍橋大學出版社與評估2024

劍橋詞典+Plus

我的主頁

+Plus 幫助

退出

詞典

定義

清晰解釋自然的書面和口頭英語

英語

學習詞典

基礎英式英語

基礎美式英語

翻譯

點選箭頭改變翻譯方向。

雙語詞典

英語-中文(簡體)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

英語-中文(繁體)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

英語-荷蘭文

荷蘭語-英語

英語-法語

法語-英語

英語-德語

德語-英語

英語-印尼語

印尼語-英語

英語-義大利語

義大利語-英語

英語-日語

日語-英語

英語-挪威語

挪威語-英語

英語-波蘭語

波蘭語-英語

英語-葡萄牙語

葡萄牙語-英語

英語-西班牙語

西班牙語-英語

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

半雙語詞典

英語-阿拉伯語

英語-孟加拉文

英語-加泰羅尼亞語

英語-捷克語

英語-丹麥語

English–Gujarati

英語-印地語

英語-韓語

英語-馬來語

英語-馬拉地語

英語-俄語

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

英語-泰語

英語-土耳其語

英語-烏克蘭文

English–Urdu

英語-越南語

翻譯

文法

同義詞詞典

Pronunciation

劍橋詞典+Plus

Shop

劍橋詞典+Plus

我的主頁

+Plus 幫助

退出

登錄 /

註冊

正體中文 (繁體)  

Change

English (UK)

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

中文 (简体)

正體中文 (繁體)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

हिंदी

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

關注我們!

選擇一本詞典

最近的詞和建議

定義

清晰解釋自然的書面和口頭英語

英語

學習詞典

基礎英式英語

基礎美式英語

文法與同義詞詞典

對自然書面和口頭英語用法的解釋

英語文法

同義詞詞典

Pronunciation

British and American pronunciations with audio

English Pronunciation

翻譯

點選箭頭改變翻譯方向。

雙語詞典

英語-中文(簡體)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

英語-中文(繁體)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

英語-荷蘭文

荷蘭語-英語

英語-法語

法語-英語

英語-德語

德語-英語

英語-印尼語

印尼語-英語

英語-義大利語

義大利語-英語

英語-日語

日語-英語

英語-挪威語

挪威語-英語

英語-波蘭語

波蘭語-英語

英語-葡萄牙語

葡萄牙語-英語

英語-西班牙語

西班牙語-英語

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

半雙語詞典

英語-阿拉伯語

英語-孟加拉文

英語-加泰羅尼亞語

英語-捷克語

英語-丹麥語

English–Gujarati

英語-印地語

英語-韓語

英語-馬來語

英語-馬拉地語

英語-俄語

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

英語-泰語

英語-土耳其語

英語-烏克蘭文

English–Urdu

英語-越南語

詞典+Plus

詞彙表

選擇語言

正體中文 (繁體)  

English (UK)

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

中文 (简体)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

हिंदी

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

內容

英語-中文(繁體) 

 Noun

例句

Translations

文法

所有翻譯

我的詞彙表

把solidarity添加到下面的一個詞彙表中,或者創建一個新詞彙表。

更多詞彙表

前往詞彙表

對該例句有想法嗎?

例句中的單詞與輸入詞條不匹配。

該例句含有令人反感的內容。

取消

提交

例句中的單詞與輸入詞條不匹配。

該例句含有令人反感的內容。

取消

提交

SOLIDARITY | English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary

SOLIDARITY | English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary

Dictionary

Translate

Grammar

Thesaurus

+Plus

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

Shop

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

My profile

+Plus help

Log out

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

My profile

+Plus help

Log out

Log in

/

Sign up

English (UK)

Search

Search

English

Meaning of solidarity in English

solidaritynoun [ U ] uk

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɒl.ɪˈdær.ə.ti/ us

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɑː.lɪˈder.ə.t̬i/

Add to word list

Add to word list

C1 agreement between and support for the members of a group, especially a political group: The situation raises important questions about solidarity among member states of the UN. The purpose of the speech was to show solidarity with the country's leaders.

Thesaurus: synonyms, antonyms, and examples

the state of agreeing with someone or somethingagreementThere's widespread agreement that something must be done.acceptanceHis views never gained acceptance among the broader community.concordanceThe study shows strong concordance between patient health and patient happiness. assentThe bill received royal assent.consentI give my consent to the marriage.sanctionShe gave official state sanction to the drilling company for their proposed pipeline.

See more results »

SMART Vocabulary: related words and phrases

Accepting & agreeing

acceptance

accepting

accommodation

accreditation

agree to something

agree with something

assent

compact

currency

presumed consent

ratification

re-establish

regrant

revalidate

rise to the bait idiom

root

rule

signatory

unquestioning

without a murmur idiom

See more results »

(Definition of solidarity from the Cambridge Advanced Learner's Dictionary & Thesaurus © Cambridge University Press)

solidarity | American Dictionary

solidaritynoun [ U ] us

Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio

/ˌsɑl·əˈdær·ɪ·t̬i/

Add to word list

Add to word list

agreement between and support for the members of a group: Hundreds of supporters gathered to show solidarity for the three men.

world history

  (also Solidarity) Solidarity is the name of a trade union (= an organization of workers) in Poland that began in 1980 and that was important in establishing free elections in 1989

(Definition of solidarity from the Cambridge Academic Content Dictionary © Cambridge University Press)

Examples of solidarity

solidarity

The latter response is reinforced in us by our obligation to stand in solidarity with victims of wrongdoing against those who have wronged them.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

As the structural dimension of solidarity had not strengthened, it was not surprising that the third hypotheses also had to be rejected.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

In terms of solidarity, the free rider has two options.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

In the absence of powerful dissenting voices, they have even been able to present this as a form of solidarity with the 'socially excluded'.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

Religious solidarity and national identity are thus forced into exclusive paradigms, which do not recognise the different narratives within each ideology.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

A positive politeness strategy highlights involvement, solidarity, and common membership, which are the essence of intimacy.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

The relationship will not always exclude maintenance of traditional clientelistic ties or ethnic solidarity.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

The motivation is more to do with protecting the inherited connection between social solidarity and national sovereignty.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

However, future studies offer the potential to compare the effects of, for example, civic duty, neighbourhood solidarity and close election messages.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

In reality, a great number of households depend on both a good monetary income and a functional solidarity system inside and outside the home.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

Prebendalism is essentially a system of shared identity and social solidarity expressing itself through a circuit which concentrates and redistributes income.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

It is perhaps in some forms of cognitive speech that the individual exhibits his solidarity both corporeal and psychical at its highest.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

They then use this model in crafting their solidarity activities and in dispensing resources.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

Each individual is integrated into various networks, each of which entails solidarities and therefore corresponding pressures.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

To this end, their chief concern was to safeguard access both to the mechanisms of traditional solidarity and to the means and factors of production.

From the Cambridge English Corpus

These examples are from corpora and from sources on the web. Any opinions in the examples do not represent the opinion of the Cambridge Dictionary editors or of Cambridge University Press or its licensors.

Collocations with solidarity

solidarity

These are words often used in combination with solidarity.Click on a collocation to see more examples of it.

act of solidarityIn turn, newspapers and government propaganda framed assistance to refugees as an act of solidarity and brotherhood which helped to strengthen the country's resolve and reconstruct national identity.

From the Cambridge English Corpus  

expression of solidarityAnd it is exactly revealing of the formation of a village identity emerging during the expression of solidarity over asserting village limits.

From the Cambridge English Corpus  

feeling of solidarityThis prompts a feeling of solidarity.

From the Cambridge English Corpus  

These examples are from corpora and from sources on the web. Any opinions in the examples do not represent the opinion of the Cambridge Dictionary editors or of Cambridge University Press or its licensors.

See all collocations with solidarity

What is the pronunciation of solidarity?

 

C1

Translations of solidarity

in Chinese (Traditional)

團結一致…

See more

in Chinese (Simplified)

团结一致…

See more

in Spanish

solidaridad…

See more

in Portuguese

solidariedade…

See more

in more languages

in Marathi

in Turkish

in French

in Dutch

in Tamil

in Hindi

in Gujarati

in Danish

in Swedish

in Malay

in German

in Norwegian

in Urdu

in Ukrainian

in Russian

in Telugu

in Bengali

in Czech

in Indonesian

in Thai

in Vietnamese

in Polish

एकजूट, गटाच्या सदस्यांमधील करार आणि समर्थन, विशेषत: राजकीय गट…

See more

dayanışma, birlik, yekvücut olma…

See more

solidarité…

See more

solidariteit…

See more

ஒரு குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு, குறிப்பாக ஒரு அரசியல் குழுவின் உறுப்பினர்களுக்கு இடையே உடன்பாடு மற்றும் ஆதரவு…

See more

(प्रायः राजनीतिक) एकजुटता…

See more

એકતા, ઐક્ય…

See more

solidaritet…

See more

solidaritet, samhörighetskänsla…

See more

perpaduan…

See more

der Zusammenhalt…

See more

solidaritet, fellesskapsfølelse…

See more

یکجہتی, ہم آہنگی…

See more

солідарність, згуртованість…

See more

солидарность…

See more

సమూహానికి, ముఖ్యంగా రాజకీయ సమూహానికి చెందిన సభ్యుల మధ్య ఒప్పందం, ఒకరికొకరి మద్దతు…

See more

সংহতি…

See more

soudržnost…

See more

solidaritas…

See more

ความสามัคคี…

See more

tình đoàn kết…

See more

solidarność…

See more

Need a translator?

Get a quick, free translation!

Translator tool

 

Browse

solid rocket

BETA

solid-state

solid-state drive

solid-state physics

BETA

solidarity

solidi

solidification

solidified

solidify

Word of the Day

flexitarian

A flexitarian way of eating consists mainly of vegetarian food but with some meat.

About this

Blog

Forget doing it or forget to do it? Avoiding common mistakes with verb patterns (2)

March 06, 2024

Read More

New Words

stochastic parrot

March 04, 2024

More new words

has been added to list

To top

Contents

EnglishAmericanExamplesCollocationsTranslations

© Cambridge University Press & Assessment 2024

Learn

Learn

Learn

New Words

Help

In Print

Word of the Year 2021

Word of the Year 2022

Word of the Year 2023

Develop

Develop

Develop

Dictionary API

Double-Click Lookup

Search Widgets

License Data

About

About

About

Accessibility

Cambridge English

Cambridge University Press & Assessment

Consent Management

Cookies and Privacy

Corpus

Terms of Use

© Cambridge University Press & Assessment 2024

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

My profile

+Plus help

Log out

Dictionary

Definitions

Clear explanations of natural written and spoken English

English

Learner’s Dictionary

Essential British English

Essential American English

Translations

Click on the arrows to change the translation direction.

Bilingual Dictionaries

English–Chinese (Simplified)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

English–Chinese (Traditional)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

English–Dutch

Dutch–English

English–French

French–English

English–German

German–English

English–Indonesian

Indonesian–English

English–Italian

Italian–English

English–Japanese

Japanese–English

English–Norwegian

Norwegian–English

English–Polish

Polish–English

English–Portuguese

Portuguese–English

English–Spanish

Spanish–English

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

Semi-bilingual Dictionaries

English–Arabic

English–Bengali

English–Catalan

English–Czech

English–Danish

English–Gujarati

English–Hindi

English–Korean

English–Malay

English–Marathi

English–Russian

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

English–Thai

English–Turkish

English–Ukrainian

English–Urdu

English–Vietnamese

Translate

Grammar

Thesaurus

Pronunciation

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

Shop

Cambridge Dictionary +Plus

My profile

+Plus help

Log out

Log in /

Sign up

English (UK)  

Change

English (UK)

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

中文 (简体)

正體中文 (繁體)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

Nederlands

Svenska

Dansk

Norsk

हिंदी

বাঙ্গালি

मराठी

ગુજરાતી

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

Українська

Follow us

Choose a dictionary

Recent and Recommended

Definitions

Clear explanations of natural written and spoken English

English

Learner’s Dictionary

Essential British English

Essential American English

Grammar and thesaurus

Usage explanations of natural written and spoken English

Grammar

Thesaurus

Pronunciation

British and American pronunciations with audio

English Pronunciation

Translation

Click on the arrows to change the translation direction.

Bilingual Dictionaries

English–Chinese (Simplified)

Chinese (Simplified)–English

English–Chinese (Traditional)

Chinese (Traditional)–English

English–Dutch

Dutch–English

English–French

French–English

English–German

German–English

English–Indonesian

Indonesian–English

English–Italian

Italian–English

English–Japanese

Japanese–English

English–Norwegian

Norwegian–English

English–Polish

Polish–English

English–Portuguese

Portuguese–English

English–Spanish

Spanish–English

English–Swedish

Swedish–English

Semi-bilingual Dictionaries

English–Arabic

English–Bengali

English–Catalan

English–Czech

English–Danish

English–Gujarati

English–Hindi

English–Korean

English–Malay

English–Marathi

English–Russian

English–Tamil

English–Telugu

English–Thai

English–Turkish

English–Ukrainian

English–Urdu

English–Vietnamese

Dictionary +Plus

Word Lists

Choose your language

English (UK)  

English (US)

Español

Русский

Português

Deutsch

Français

Italiano

中文 (简体)

正體中文 (繁體)

Polski

한국어

Türkçe

日本語

Tiếng Việt

Nederlands

Svenska

Dansk

Norsk

हिंदी

বাঙ্গালি

मराठी

ગુજરાતી

தமிழ்

తెలుగు

Українська

Contents

English 

 Noun

American 

 Noun

Examples

Collocations

Translations

Grammar

All translations

My word lists

Add solidarity to one of your lists below, or create a new one.

More

Go to your word lists

Tell us about this example sentence:

The word in the example sentence does not match the entry word.

The sentence contains offensive content.

Cancel

Submit

The word in the example sentence does not match the entry word.

The sentence contains offensive content.

Cancel

Submit

Solidarity Definition & Meaning - Merriam-Webster

Solidarity Definition & Meaning - Merriam-Webster

Menu Toggle

Merriam-Webster Logo

Games & Quizzes

Games & Quizzes

Word of the Day

Grammar

Wordplay

Word Finder

Thesaurus

Join MWU

Shop

Books

Merch

Settings

My Words

Recents

Account

Log Out

More

Thesaurus

Join MWU

Shop

Books

Merch

Log In

Username

My Words

Recents

Account

Log Out

Est. 1828

Dictionary

Definition

Definition

Example Sentences

Word History

Related Articles

Entries Near

Cite this EntryCitation

Share

Kids DefinitionKids

Legal DefinitionLegal

More from M-W

Show more

Show more

Citation

Share

Kids

Legal

More from M-W

Save Word

To save this word, you'll need to log in.

Log In

solidarity

noun

sol·​i·​dar·​i·​ty

ˌsä-lə-ˈder-ə-tē 

-ˈda-rə-

Synonyms of solidarity

: unity (as of a group or class) that produces or is based on community of interests, objectives, and standards

Examples of solidarity in a Sentence

The vote was a show of solidarity.

Recent Examples on the Web

The Houthis, who control much of Yemen including the capital Sanaa, have said their attacks off the coast of Yemen are a show of solidarity for Palestinians facing Israeli attacks in Gaza.

—Emma Bowman, NPR, 24 Feb. 2024

And in a rare display of solidarity, many of the jurors who had taken just over two hours to convict Walton, re-entered the courtroom to hear the family speak and listen to the sentencing.

—Charles Rabin, Miami Herald, 22 Feb. 2024

In solidarity, Sam’s teammates boycott the sponsor alongside him on the field, covering up the company logo on their jerseys.

—Melissa Jun Rowley, Rolling Stone, 22 Feb. 2024

Last fall, it was reported that the White House had circulated a somber, confidential analysis that solidarity for Ukraine among allies might crumble without additional concrete steps being taken to stem the perception of corruption that still bedevils the country.

—James P. Moore Jr., Fortune Europe, 22 Feb. 2024

The judge ruled then that it was not protected because employees were showing solidarity with the Black Lives Matter movement, without any goal related to their working conditions at the store.

—Ramishah Maruf, CNN, 21 Feb. 2024

People who wore masks and people who did not weren’t simply members of different clans: the ones with masks were making a gesture toward social solidarity and signalling a reluctance to infect their neighbors; the ones without were affirming selfishness as a principle of conduct.

—Adam Gopnik, The New Yorker, 19 Feb. 2024

Both candidates expressed unwavering support for Israel in its conflict with Hamas, even appearing side-by-side in an unusual joint event intended to convey solidarity.

—Anthony Izaguirre, Fortune, 14 Feb. 2024

So here, the consensus model leads to social solidarity wherein collective conscience operates as a unifying force within the society.

—Sindhu Bhaskar, Forbes, 13 Feb. 2024

See More

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word 'solidarity.' Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

Word History

Etymology

French solidarité, from solidaire characterized by solidarity, from Latin solidum whole sum, from neuter of solidus solid

First Known Use

1841, in the meaning defined above

Time Traveler

The first known use of solidarity was

in 1841

See more words from the same year

Articles Related to solidarity

The Words of the Week - 6/12/20

Some of the words that defined the week ending June 12, 2020

Dictionary Entries Near solidarity

solidarism

solidarity

solidarize

See More Nearby Entries 

Cite this Entry

Style

MLA

Chicago

APA

Merriam-Webster

“Solidarity.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary, Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/solidarity. Accessed 9 Mar. 2024.

Copy Citation

Share

Post the Definition of solidarity to Facebook

Facebook

Share the Definition of solidarity on Twitter

Twitter

Kids Definition

solidarity

noun

sol·​i·​dar·​i·​ty

ˌsäl-ə-ˈdar-ət-ē 

: unity (as of a group) that produces or is based on shared interests and goals

Legal Definition

solidarity

noun

sol·​i·​dar·​i·​ty

ˌsä-lə-ˈdar-ə-tē 

in the civil law of Louisiana

: the quality or state of being solidary : existence of a solidary obligation

will not presume solidarity

More from Merriam-Webster on solidarity

Thesaurus: All synonyms and antonyms for solidarity

Nglish: Translation of solidarity for Spanish Speakers

Britannica English: Translation of solidarity for Arabic Speakers

Britannica.com: Encyclopedia article about solidarity

Last Updated:

28 Feb 2024

- Updated example sentences

Love words? Need even more definitions?

Subscribe to America's largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!

Merriam-Webster unabridged

Can you solve 4 words at once?

Play

Play

Can you solve 4 words at once?

Play

Play

Word of the Day

germane

See Definitions and Examples »

Get Word of the Day daily email!

Popular in Grammar & Usage

See All

8 Grammar Terms You Used to Know, But Forgot

Homophones, Homographs, and Homonyms

Your vs. You're: How to Use Them Correctly

Every Letter Is Silent, Sometimes: A-Z List of Examples

More Commonly Mispronounced Words

See All

Popular in Wordplay

See All

10 Lesser-Known Reduplications

The Words of the Week - Mar. 8

10 Scrabble Words Without Any Vowels

12 More Bird Names that Sound Like Insults (and Sometimes Are)

8 Uncommon Words Related to Love

See All

Games & Quizzes

See All

Quordle

Can you solve 4 words at once?

Play

Blossom Word Game

You can make only 12 words. Pick the best ones!

Play

Missing Letter

A crossword with a twist

Play

Spelling Bee Quiz

Can you outdo past winners of the National Spelli...

Take the quiz

Merriam Webster

Learn a new word every day. Delivered to your inbox!

Help

About Us

Advertising Info

Contact Us

Diversity

Privacy Policy

Terms of Use

Facebook

Twitter

YouTube

Instagram

© 2024 Merriam-Webster, Incorporated

Just a moment...

a moment...Enable JavaScript and cookies to continue

Solidarity in Social and Political Philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Solidarity in Social and Political Philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Menu

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Entry Navigation

Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Friends PDF Preview

Author and Citation Info

Back to Top

Solidarity in Social and Political PhilosophyFirst published Sat Mar 25, 2023

The term “solidarity” first becomes prevalent in the

early- to late-nineteenth century in France. Since then, it has always

been used to describe a special relationship of unity and mutual

indebtedness within a group. The term’s origins lie in French

legal usage, in which the Roman legal concept of an obligation in

solidum—a joint contractual obligation in which each

signatory declared himself liable for the debts of all

together—long had a place in the French code civile

(Blais 2007; Hayward 1959; Wildt 1999). Solidarity expands beyond its

legal origins to become a central social and political concept in

response to anxiety about the centrifugal, individualizing forces of

commercial and industrial society. What could replace the old social

ties of church, family, and guild, all of which had been weakened by

markets? What might ensure a sense of shared purpose and common good?

As an answer to these questions, “solidarity” becomes a

rallying cry in progressive movements across Europe, including

socialism, liberal nationalism, Catholic reformism, and

Solidarism.

More recently, there has been a resurgence not only in calls for

solidarity but also in theorizing about solidarity. Solidarity has

been invoked with increasing regularity in contemporary social

movements (Movement for Black Lives, Occupy, MeToo, climate change

activism), law and politics (COVID, EU, constitutions around the

world, human rights), and even bioethics. There is a growing

literature in sociology, political science, social theory, and social

and political philosophy on the concept and its value. And yet, the

idea remains hard to pin down: What is solidarity? And what, if

anything, makes it valuable? In this entry, we aim to provide an

overview of this recent debate, focusing on its development in social

and political philosophy.

1. The Nature of Solidarity

2. Solidarity in Practice

2.1 Socialism

2.2 Civic Solidarity

2.3 National Solidarity

2.4 Christian Solidarity

2.5 Solidarity in social movements

2.6 Conclusion

3. The Value of Solidarity

4. Challenges to Solidarity

4.1 Theoretical criticism of solidarity

4.1.1 Conceptual incoherence

4.1.2 Theoretical redundancy

4.2 Practical challenges to Solidarity

4.2.1 Does solidarity threaten liberty?

4.2.2 Does solidarity promote false beliefs?

4.2.3 Is solidarity exclusionary / unfair towards outsiders?

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. The Nature of Solidarity

In social and political philosophy, the concept of solidarity is

primarily used to evaluate, guide, and describe activities within

groups and between individuals and groups. In unpacking different

accounts, it is useful to begin by listing some typical

practice-embedded expressions in which the concept is used. In a

conversation about our work environment, someone might say, “we

should show more solidarity with one another”; in a conversation

about the origins of the welfare state, someone might say, “the

welfare state is an expression of solidarity among citizens”; in

a conversation about the dynamics of social movements, someone might

say, “the neo-Nazi protesters acted in solidarity with one

another”; in a conversation about supporting the Movement for

Black Lives (M4BL), someone might say, “I stand in solidarity

with you in fighting oppression”; in a conversation about the

moral values animating European integration as a project, someone

might say, “solidarity is a foundational value of the European

Union”; in a conversation about the downsides of investment

banking, someone might say, “there is not much solidarity among

bankers”; in a conversation about the plight of earthquake

victims in Indonesia, someone might say, “solidarity requires

that we send some money as soon as possible”; in responding to

news that a teammate has cancer, someone might say: “we ought to

shave our heads in solidarity”. What accounts of the concept can

aid us in evaluating and describing the phenomenon referred to in

these and similar circumstances?

At the broadest level, philosophers (such as O’Neill 1996: 201

and Miller 2017: 62) usually distinguish between two senses of

solidarity: solidarity among and solidarity with.

According to the former, solidarity describes a relation among members

of the same social group. As we will see in more detail below,

solidarity among usually requires a rough symmetry in the

attitudes and dispositions of its members. For example, we might both

identify as members of Danish nation, share a commitment to overthrow

the occupiers, and each be willing to come to each other’s aid

in fighting them. On the other hand, solidarity with

describes a relation between an individual and another individual, or

between a set of individuals and the members of a social group of

which the former are not members (the “outgroup”). On this

reading, symmetry is not required: I might act in solidarity with you

as an earthquake victim when I wire money to an NGO that is operative

in your city. Here I act in solidarity with you without your acting in

solidarity with me (or even being disposed to act in solidarity with

me were the tables to be turned). A paradigmatic example of

solidarity with is the Catholic notion of solidarity

understood as a form of caritas, or charity (on an

alternative interpretation of solidarity in the Catholic tradition,

see below). As Józef Tischner, who was influential in

Poland’s solidarity movement, writes:

With whom, therefore, is our solidarity? It is, above all, with those

who have been wounded by other people, with those who suffer pain that

could be avoided—accidental, needless pain. This does not

preclude solidarity with others, with all who suffer. However, the

solidarity with those who suffer at the hands of others is

particularly vital, strong, spontaneous. (Tischner 1982 [1984]:

8–9)

Philosophers divide on whether asymmetric, unilateral forms of aid and

support from individuals to other individuals, or from outgroup

members to ingroups counts as genuine solidarity. For some

(see, e.g., Sangiovanni forthcoming), they do not. We do better, he

argues, not to conceive of solidarity with as a form of

solidarity at all. The unilateral, asymmetric reading, he argues,

tends to vitiate the egalitarianism at the heart of solidarity, and

does not fit well with the practices in which the term was,

historically, most prevalent. He also argues that solidarity

with in this narrower sense is not distinguishable from other,

related terms, such as “humanitarian aid”,

“charity”, “benevolence”, or “support

for a good cause”. There is nothing gained in calling forms of

humanitarian aid or support for a good cause “solidarity”,

and running the two ideas together under a single banner tends to

obscure the value of solidarity as a form of egalitarian collective

action.

For other philosophers (e.g., Kolers 2016), solidarity (whether

with or among) must always be unilateral

and asymmetric. Kolers argues that paradigmatic cases of solidarity

involve one group or individual (usually members of an outgroup),

S, deferring to an object group, G, but not

vice versa. According to Kolers,

[solidary action] is not principally justified by appeal to goals, nor

do we choose sides on the basis of shared goals. To the contrary, when

S is in solidarity with G, it is G, not

G’s ends, that S endorses or values. S is

disposed to adopt whatever goal G sets for the action

or as a political aim. For instance, insofar as they are in

solidarity, heterosexual persons who support the right of same-sex

couples to marry do so not because they individually want same-sex

marriages to be possible, but because the LGBTQ community treats that

as an important goal. (Kolers 2016: 58)

Paradigmatic instances of solidarity involve members of (out)groups

(e.g., heterosexuals) committing themselves to do whatever members of

a disadvantaged (in)group (e.g., homosexuals) require to overcome

injustice. Importantly, on this picture outgroup members commit to the

group, rather than to any aim pursued by the group. As a

heterosexual, I do not act in solidarity by committing

directly to fighting heterosexism alongside members of the LGBTQ

community; rather, to act in solidarity, I must commit to the LGBTQ

community as such, and so to whatever members tell me I need to do to

promote their cause, whatever cause that is.

One advantage of this view is that it captures an important ethical

aspect of coalitional social movements in which more privileged

(out)groups act as allies of less privileged (in)groups in fighting

injustice. As has often been noted, the trouble with such coalitions

is that members of privileged groups often tend to be blind to the way

in which privilege colors and sometimes distorts their efforts to

support the aims of the

movement.[1]

Outgroup allies can sometimes reproduce, unconsciously, wider

structural patterns of power and exclusion as they fight alongside

ingroup members; they can perpetrate, for example, forms of epistemic

injustice in seeking to impose their own agenda or ideals onto the

wider movement (Deveaux 2021; Clark 2014; Medina 2013; Gould 2020;

Land 2015). Kolers’ work reminds his readers that genuine

solidarity requires that members of outgroups put aside their

particular concerns, ideals, prejudices, and so on, and

listen (Kolers 2016: 115). They must be prepared, in turn, to

accept their relative epistemic limitations vis-à-vis members

of ingroups who not only have “skin in the game” but often

a vivid lived experience of the forms of injustice they are fighting.

And they must also be prepared to defer out of respect for the

disadvantaged: whether or not the disadvantaged have better epistemic

access to truths about the struggle, etc., the privileged ought to

defer out of respect for what is at stake for the

disadvantaged.[2]

So far, we have discussed unilateral, asymmetric accounts of our

target concept. We now turn to accounts of the concept that treat the

idea of solidarity among as paradigmatic. Rather than naming

the set of attitudes and actions characteristic of an individual who

(unilaterally) offers support or aid, the idea of solidarity

among names a relation among members of the

same group. The relation is generally understood to make it

the case that the group exhibits a distinctive kind of unity

among its members (solidus in Latin means whole or

integrated). But what kind of unity? The unity in question is

composed, on all plausible views, by an interlocking set of attitudes,

dispositions, and characteristic actions displayed by members. It is

useful to compare relations of solidarity to the relations

constituting social groups as such. According to one

influential definition of a social group, a social group

is a collection of individuals who perceive themselves to be members

of the same social category, share some emotional involvement in this

common definition of themselves, and achieve some degree of social

consensus about the evaluation of their group and their membership of

it. (Tajfel & Turner 2001: 100).

People waiting at a bus stop, or boarding a train, are not, in normal

circumstances, a social group; employees of Google and members of the

Church of England are. We can then say: For an (in)group to display

solidarity, it must recognize itself as a social group: members must

identify themselves based on some characteristic that marks them out

as a social group. For example, members might identify as

workers (on the basis, that is, of a role), as black

(on the basis of racial

categorization[3]),

as cancer survivors (on the basis of a common set of

experiences), as environmentalists (on the basis of a shared

cause), and so

on.[4]

But what other conditions are necessary (or at least paradigmatic)?

Identifying as a social group is not sufficient: it seems clear that

we might identify as employees of Google, or as engineers, or as

investment bankers, but not be in solidarity with one another.

An obvious candidate is the condition that members of the social group

be disposed to put aside narrow self-interest in coming to each

other’s aid when required. We might imagine, for example, that

the employees of Google or investment bankers are not prepared to set

aside narrow self-interest except in special circumstances (where,

say, employees know one another independently). If this were true,

then it seems clear that, in their normal everyday interactions, they

wouldn’t be in solidarity with one another (despite their

cooperation). Some philosophers believe that these two

conditions—identifying as a member of a social group and a

willingness, on that basis, to set aside narrow self-interest in

coming to a fellow’s aid—are necessary and

sufficient for solidarity. Philippe Van Parijs, for example,

writes:

When I help you out of solidarity, I do so because you are “one

of us”, because “I could have been you”, because, in

this sense, I “identify” with you. (Van Parijs

forthcoming; see also Mason 2000: 27)

To illustrate, Van Parijs gives the example of a fellow traveler

returning a lost wallet, or a cyclist helping another to board a

train. In both cases, someone identifies as a traveler (or as a

cyclist) and, in virtue of that identification, is disposed to come to

another traveler or cyclist’s aid.

An advantage of the view is that it can encompass a wide variety of

different contexts. It can, for example, account for

unilateral senses of solidarity, such as the Good Samaritan.

As long as the Good Samaritan is motivated by a relevant

self-categorization that includes the stranger, then his coming to his

aid counts as solidarity. The Good Samaritan might feel disposed to

aid because he has shared the experience of being a victim of

injustice, or because of their shared vulnerability, say, as human

beings. But its encompassing nature may also make it hard to

distinguish from related notions. The account seems to collapse into

the view that solidarity is another name for all responsibilities that

flow (or that are perceived to flow) from membership in a social

group.

Tommie Shelby offers a view that is broadly similar in structure, but

strengthens the requirements for mutual identification and group

cohesion. For Shelby,

I believe there are five core normative requirements that are jointly

sufficient for a robust form of solidarity [identification with the

group, special concern, shared values or goals, loyalty, and mutual

trust]. By “robust” I mean a solidarity that is strong

enough to move people to collective action, not just mutual sympathy

born of recognition of communality or a mere sense of group belonging.

(Shelby 2005: 68; see also May 1996: 44; cf. Feinberg 1973: 677)

Returning a lost wallet and the Good Samaritan, on this view, are

ruled out since they are products of a weak sense of group belonging.

One may object, however, that the view is still not restrictive

enough. For example, a reading group might exhibit all five features,

and move its participants to do things together, and yet it seems

strained to say that a reading group is in solidarity with one

another. (It is strained not so much because it doesn’t capture

the ordinary English meaning, but because it seems to jar with the

value and history of the practices in which the term has predominantly

figured, and which make sense of the role we might want an account of

solidarity to play.) It is also unclear, on this view, whether

collective action is a necessary condition of solidarity, or whether

two or more people can be in solidarity by holding the attitudes

mentioned without ever acting together in some relevant sense. Might

brothers be in solidarity by possessing all five of the listed

attitudes, though they never act together in the pursuit of any goals,

or come to each other’s aid in any way?

Sally Scholz offers a view of solidarity that is explicitly political

and oppositional. For Scholz,

Political solidarity arises in opposition to something; it is a

movement for social change that may occur at many levels of social

existence. … Natural disasters may inspire strong sentiments

and even bonds of connection, but they do not inspire political

solidarity. Political solidarity as I present it has a social justice

content or aim; it opposes injustice, oppression, tyranny, and social

vulnerabilities. (Scholz 2008: 54; see also Mohanty 2003:

7)[5]

Solidarity, on this view, is always geared toward overcoming

injustice; it is essentially political. The reading group would be

excluded, and so would be the Good Samaritan and sending money to

earthquake victims. Scholz also argues that the concept entails the

existence of positive moral obligations among participants. If

participants (for example, a white supremacist group) lack positive

obligations to aid each other in protesting racial integration

(because such a protest would be in the service of unjust ends), then

they cannot act in solidarity when they protest, come to each

other’s aid, and are committed to their cause.

Andrea Sangiovanni offers a view that is less restrictive (but more

restrictive than Shelby’s). In contrast to Scholz, he argues

that solidarity must always be aimed at overcoming adversity, but the

adversity need not be political. For example, suppose a village burns

down in a fire and residents band together to rebuild it. They are

committed to the endeavor and are ready to come to each other’s

aid. Because their endeavor is oriented toward overcoming shared

adversity it counts as solidarity. Furthermore, for Sangiovanni, the

concept solidarity is not moralized: even mafiosi can be in solidarity

with one another (despite the fact, that is, that their solidarity

will promote bad ends). Finally, solidarity, he claims, neither merely

precedes collective action (or, as Shelby argues, makes it

more likely) nor is it merely a by-product of collective

action, but is itself a form of collective action. As a kind

of action, it does not therefore name only a set of desires and

beliefs, a virtue, or a sense of fellowship with others. Rather,

solidarity is any instance of collective action that has the following

core features:

Participants identify with one another on the basis of a role,

condition, cause, set of experiences, or way of life on the basis of

which …

… they each …

…intend to do their part in overcoming some significant

adversity, X, by pursuing, together, some more proximate shared

goal, Y;

… are individually committed (i) to X and Y

and (ii) to not bypassing each other’s will in the achievement

of X and Y;

… are committed to sharing one another’s fates in

ways relevant to X and Y.

… trust one another to play their part in X and

Y, trust each other’s commitment, trust that each will

not bypass the other’s will, and trust each to share the

other’s fate.

This view faces a number of challenges as well. First, like Shelby and

Scholz, it doesn’t allow for unilateral cases of

solidarity—such as the Good Samaritan and sending money to

earthquake victims—to count as instances of solidarity since

there is no collective action in the required sense. Second, and

relatedly, it doesn’t allow for cases of “silent” or

“private” solidarity (Bommarito 2016; Zhao 2019). As a

young girl, Simone Weil gave up eating sugar because sugar had become

unavailable to soldiers at the front. It seems plausible to say that

she acted in solidarity with the soldiers. What reasons do we

have to rule such cases out? And, finally, it seems to rule out

protest movements that are organized on behalf of victims of

injustice but not with them. Imagine we organize a protest

against the French government’s closure of the refugee camps in

Calais, and suppose that the refugees there do not know of, or

otherwise take part in, our protest. Sangiovanni’s account seems

to force us to say that we, on the outside, act in solidarity with one

another but not with the refugees.

2. Solidarity in Practice

So far, we have discussed the nature of solidarity in general. In this

section, we review the social and political practices in which the

term has primarily figured. Whatever account of the general concept we

think is best should aid us in illuminating each of these contexts (by

successfully describing, evaluating, and guiding them). In the

following, however, we remain neutral between different accounts of

the general concept. Furthermore, we only cover a sample of such

contexts. There are many more practices in which solidarity has found

a place. We focus on what strike us as the historically most important

and influential ones.

2.1 Socialism

As mentioned above, the idea becomes prevalent in the early-nineteenth

century in France. The soil in which the concept first takes root is

socialism. The early socialist writers—Robert Owen

(1771–1858), Henri de Saint-Simon (1760–1825), and Charles

Fourier (1772–1837) (who Marx and Engels would later dismiss as

“utopian”) were especially influential—decried the

individualism and egoism fostered by market society (Claeys 2011). The

untethering of markets from constraints of traditional law, social

structures, and morality inevitably led, they argued, to social

conflict and the moral, economic, and cultural degradation of the

working classes. They believed that new forms of mutual aid,

cooperation, and association were needed to bring each functional unit

of the modern industrial economy together in a mutually supportive

web, and prevent the worst effects of the competitive division of

labor and the poverty it produces. In 1826, Robert Owen wrote:

There is but one mode … by which man can possess in perpetuity

all the happiness which his nature is capable of enjoying,—that

is by the union and co-operation of all for the benefit of

each. While mankind remain congregated in large cities and

towns, or live in single families apart from their species, each

having distinct and opposite interests, no substantial improvement can

be effected in the condition of society. To obtain the full advantages

of cooperation, men must be associated in small communities, or large

families, all the members of which shall be united by the bond of one

common interest; the same bond of union connecting each community with

every other established on similar principles. (Owen 1826–27

[2016: 69]; see also Leopold 2015)

Hippolyte Renaud gave this unified, mutually supportive social

cooperation in the service of each and all a name that formed the

title of his immensely popular summary of Fourier’s works,

namely Solidarité

(1842).[6]

In “Socialism: Utopian and Scientific” (1876), Engels

rejected the utopians’ for failing to explain how their proposed

societies could ever be realized (1876 [1978: 685ff]). There was no

basis for their doctrines or their faith in the empirically verifiable

laws of society. Given its association with the

“utopians”, it is revealing that neither Marx nor Engels

ever used “solidarity” as a term in any of their

systematic writings. Where they did use the term was in their speeches

and letters regarding the workingmen’s associations that were

springing up everywhere in defense of socialism. In 1872, in a speech

given in Amsterdam after a congress of the First International, Marx

says:

Citizens, let us think of the basic principle of the International:

Solidarity. Only when we have established this life-giving principle

on a sound basis among the numerous workers of all countries will we

attain the great final goal which we have set ourselves. The

revolution must be carried out with solidarity; this is the great

lesson of the French Commune, which fell because none of the other

centers—Berlin, Madrid, etc.—developed great revolutionary

movements comparable to the mighty uprising of the Paris proletariat.

(Marx 1872 [1978: 522])

And, as Karl Kautsky, one of the most influential Marxists in the late

nineteenth century, writes in the Class Struggle, which was

the German Social Democratic Party’s official commentary on the

proposed Erfurt program of 1891:

But as soon as the workers discover that their interests are common,

that they are all opposed to the exploiter, it takes the form of great

organizations and open battles against the exploiting class.…

And when [these elevating tendencies] have once wakened full

class-consciousness in any group of workers, the consciousness of

solidarity with all the members of the working-class, the

consciousness of the strength that is born of union; as soon as any

group has recognized that it is essential to society and that it dare

hope for better things in the future,—then it is well nigh

impossible to shove that group back into the degenerate mass of beings

whose opposition to the system under which they suffer takes no other

form than that of unreasoned hate. (Kautsky 1892: Ch. 5,

Secs. 5–6; see also Wildt 1999)

From its early socialist origins, “solidarity” found its

natural home as a term describing the unity of workers’

associations—a term describing, that is, their mutual

identification with one another as exploited, their mutual commitment

to overthrowing capitalism through organized cooperation, and their

willingness to sacrifice for one another in the name of the cause.

2.2 Civic Solidarity

Civic solidarity refers to solidarity among citizens of modern states,

and is often associated with the emergence and development of welfare

states. The term as used in this way first became popular in the

late-nineteenth century in France. The late-nineteenth century usages

are outgrowths of earlier forms of socialism, but they develop the

idea in directions that are less oppositional than the socialism that

emerges as a political force in the wake of 1848. Two figures are

associated with its popularization during this period: Léon

Bourgeois and Emile Durkheim. We start with Léon Bourgeois

since his account was, at the time, more influential than

Durkheim’s.

In 1896, Léon Bourgeois—prime minister of France from

1895–6—published what would become the programmatic

manifesto of the Solidarist movement, namely a pamphlet entitled

Solidarité (Bourgeois 1902). The pamphlet begins by

noting that all complex organisms reproduce themselves through an

internal division of labor. Each organ has a different function; their

interdependence is organized in such a way as to ensure the

being’s self-preservation. Bourgeois calls this internal unity

natural solidarity. He then goes on to note that societies

are organized in much the same way: the more complex a society is, the

more diverse and interdependent its internal division of labor. There

are two differences. The first difference is that societies are made

up of individuals possessed of reason and will, and so the laws of

nature are not sufficient to ensure that the parts will coordinate to

sustain and reproduce the life of the whole. The second difference

follows directly from the first. Because the coordination necessary to

maintain and reproduce a society depends on the reason and will of

individuals, the laws that govern that reproduction must also work via

those very same faculties. The laws governing social

solidarity are, therefore, necessarily moral.

What mores ought to govern the division of labor and so,

ultimately, the distribution of the benefits and burdens of joint

production (la répartition des profits et des

charges)? Bourgeois writes that we must look for an answer at the

moral implications of the very reciprocal dependence that constitutes

society in the first place. Once we do so, we will see that every

individual within the societal division of labor owes the vast

preponderance of what they are able to obtain from that

society—for example, through their talents and abilities, or

through the knowledge they acquire from that society—to two

sources. First, they owe a debt to past generations and, second, to

contemporaries who, in the present, reproduce and advance the

institutions, knowledge, resources, and societal conventions from

which they gain (almost) all that is theirs.

[Because of man’s dependence on the societal division of labor]

a necessary exchange of services exists between each and all. The free

development of his faculties, of his activities, in short, of his very

being, can only be realized, for each individual, as a result

of the concurrent contributions of other men’s faculties and

activities. This free development can, furthermore, only reach its

full extent as a result of the accumulated contributions of the

past.

There is therefore a debt owed by each to all the rest, in virtue of

the contributions and services rendered by all to each. (Bourgeois

1902: 137, translation by Sangiovanni)

Moral solidarity requires, then, citizens to identify with

one another as jointly responsible for the social product, and to be

prepared to discharge the social debt through common institutions

designed to insure people against unemployment, sickness, and old age,

to maintain jobs open to talents, and to support a public system of

education. Lack of moral solidarity, Bourgeois implies, will lead

inevitably to lack of coordination among the parts, and so to a

breakdown in natural solidarity.

Published a few years earlier than Bourgeois’ pamphlet,

Durkheim’s doctoral thesis—The Division of Labor in

Society (1893)—distinguished between the

mechanical solidarity typical of premodern, less complex

societies and the organic solidarity of modern industrialized

societies. Societies whose social cohesion is founded on mechanical

solidarity are integrated through a “collective

consciousness” that defines a common way of life. Where

mechanical solidarity is characterized by similarity among

members of a society, organic solidarity is characterized by

difference. At the heart of organic solidarity is, as it was

for Bourgeois, the division of labor. Modern societies must be

integrated via the coordinated interdependence of an extensive

division of labor. But Durkheim is adamant that the coordinated

functioning of the different parts is not self-regulating. He

emphasizes the need for a diffuse moral solidarity to

reinforce and stabilize the functioning of the division of labor.

(Top-down regulation via the state—which is “too

remote” and “general”—is also not enough

[Durkheim 1893 [1984: 27]].) This solidarity can no longer come from

the “collective consciousness” (as it did in premodern

societies): the differentiation of modern society increases

individualism and diversity, undoing the bonds of similarity that tie

together premodern societies. What sources are left to support the

mutual “attraction”, disposition to come to other’s

aid, and trust required for the cohesion of a society?

His proposed solution is clearest in the Second Preface to the

Division of Labor, added in 1902. He suggests that the state

alone cannot guarantee the conditions necessary for maintaining

solidarity against the three predominant causes of social unrest in

modern, differentiated societies. The first cause is anomie,

the loss of direction and orientation that can accompany

specialization. Anomie is the primary social danger accompanying the

growing depth and extent of the division of labor, and threatens the

sense in which we each are essential contributors to the success of

society as a whole (Durkheim 1893/1902 [1984: 289–90]). The

second cause is force, the sense of injustice that arises

from a feeling that one’s work is not valued according to its

worth and one’s own merits—the sense, in short, that one

is exploited. Such grievances are especially strong when premodern

elements of caste persist in modern conditions. The third cause is

disuse, or the aimlessness, resentment, and lack of focus

that comes from not having enough work. In each case, Durkheim argues,

the citizen comes to lose a grip on his larger place in reproducing

the whole; as he turns inwards, his grievances seem to him larger and

his duties to others less pressing; he is less fulfilled by his labor,

seeing it no longer as a reflection of his nature; mistrust takes

root; he no longer sees his potential employers as cooperative

partners, but begins to see them as enemies.

In the Preface, he argues that only the “professional grouping

is a moral force capable of curbing individual egoism” (Durkheim

1893/1902 [1984: 11]). By “professional grouping”,

Durkheim meant that the various industrial branches of an economy

would be grouped into corporations (modelled on the feudal

corporation). Unlike unions, corporations would constituted by both

employers and employees, and would have the power to regulate wages,

conditions of work, appointments and promotions; they would also have

the authority to coordinate with other branches and with government.

The effect of such groupings would be to recreate solidarity where it

was most under pressure:

Within a political society [e.g., a corporation], as soon as a certain

number of individuals find they hold in common ideas, interests,

sentiments and occupations which the rest of the population does not

share in, it is inevitable that, under the influence of these

similarities, they should be attracted to one another. … It is

impossible for men to live together and be in regular contact with one

another without their acquiring some feeling for the totality which

they constitute through having united together, without their becoming

attached to it, concerning themselves with its interests and taking it

into account in their behaviour. (Durkheim 1893/1902 [1984:

17–8])

The idea was that, in grouping together in smaller, functionally

organized units individuals would regain their sense of contributing

to society while, at the same time, giving everyone a felt stake in

the justice and fairness required to reproduce it. In sum, organic

solidarity refers to the bonds of mutual sacrifice and attraction that

develop when each citizen realizes how the contribution they make to

the overall functioning of the society as a whole, via their economic

and social role, depends on a tightly knit, interdependent web of more

particular associations.

2.3 National Solidarity

The nineteenth-century nationalist takes over the term from the

socialists to describe the unity of a nation in its struggle about

external forces. For the nationalist, solidarity is anchored in shared

identification with an “imagined community” where

membership is defined not in terms of class or social position, but in

terms of an underlying way of life characterized by common folkways,

mores, and a shared history of struggle. In 1882, Ernest Renan claimed

that the nation is an expression of a

great solidarity (une grande solidarité), constituted

by a sense of the common sacrifices that have been made and that one

is disposed to make again. (Renan 1882: 29)

And Giuseppe Mazzini, whose version of liberal-republican nationalism

was to have such a great influence on nationalist movements across the

world, writes in 1871:

The individual’s means and his thirty or forty years of adult

life are but a tiny drop in the vast Ocean of existence. As soon as he

becomes aware of this, he ends up discouraged and abandons the entire

undertaking. If he is a good man, he will now and again engage in

simple charity. If he is evil, he will isolate himself in complete

selfishness. But give this man a Country [patria] and

establish a link of solidarity [solidarietà] between

his individual efforts and the efforts of all subsequent generations;

place him in association with the labors of 25 to 30 million men who

speak the same language, have similar habits and beliefs, profess

faith in the same goal, and have developed specific tools for

their work as required by the general conditions of their land, and

the problem will change for him at once: his strengths will be greatly

multiplied, allowing him to feel up to the task. (“Nazionalismo

e Nazionalità” 1871 [2009: 63])

On this understanding, the nation is understood primarily as a project

in which each participates over time and across generations. This same

understanding has carried over to contemporary nationalists. For

them,

a common history, territory, and shared bonds of belonging give rise

to a commitment to a common project, namely to reproduce and defend

the patria. As in workers’ movements, the struggle,

furthermore, requires a preparedness to come to each other’s aid

in realizing the project.

2.4 Christian Solidarity

Solidarity becomes increasingly important in Christian, especially

Catholic, thought and practice beginning at the end of the nineteenth

century and takes flight with the papacy of John Paul

II.[7]

In response to the rising importance of socialism and class conflict

in the middle of the nineteenth century, the Church realizes the need

to address the situation of the worker. In the Church’s

response, Pope Leo XIII’s Rerum Novarum (1891)—a

staple of Catholic social thought—tries to steal a march on the

socialists by incorporating and reworking one of the socialist’s

main rallying points, namely the idea of mutualism within

worker’s associations. In those passages, Leo cites Ecclesiastes

approvingly on the importance of fraternity:

“It is better that two should be together than one; for they

have the advantage of their society. If one fall he shall be supported

by the other. Woe to him that is alone, for when he falleth he hath

none to lift him up”. And further: “A brother that is

helped by his brother is like a strong city”. It is this natural

impulse which binds men together in civil society; and it is likewise

this which leads them to join together in associations. (Leo XIII

1891: §50)

But it was not until much later that the term gets used explicitly. In

the 1967 encyclical Populorum Progressio, on global

development and the inequality between rich and poor nations, Pope

Paul VI invokes the unmistakably Solidarist notion that

interdependence creates social obligations:

We are the heirs of earlier generations, and we reap benefits from the

efforts of our contemporaries; we are under obligation to all men.

Therefore we cannot disregard the welfare of those who will come after

us to increase the human family. The reality of human solidarity

brings us not only benefits but also obligations. (§17)

The origin of the Church’s union of interdependence and

solidarity lies in an earlier nineteenth-century current of thought

often referred to as Christian Solidarism. In Ethics and the

National Economy (1918), its founder and most prominent advocate,

Heinrich Pesch (1854–1926), writes:

Christianity teaches us that people, despite all individual and also

social differences in occupation and ownership, are nevertheless

socii, i.e., comrades, precisely by virtue of those

differences. They are dependent on each other and bound together by a

solidaristic community of interests in all of their

industrial relationships as masters and journeymen, as employers and

workers, and in the human race overall, which is the great universal

family of nations. (Pesch 1918 [2004: 104])

On this corporatist understanding, it is not just the shared

experience of human suffering, or the understanding of the human being

as imago dei, but a recognition of the interdependence of

human beings in society that grounds a demand to share one

another’s fate. On this picture, we are meant to recognize how

both our flourishing and our suffering is a result of mutual influence

and mutual reliance in and through the multiple associations to which

we belong; in response, we have obligations to share others’

fates by coming to others’ aid and by limiting the harm we

do.

As is widely recognized, John Paul II was also deeply influenced by

this strand of Catholic Social Thought (and its realization in Leo

XIII’s Rerum

Novarum).[8]

In Sollicitudo rei socialis, he writes:

When interdependence becomes recognized […], the correlative

response as a moral and social attitude, as a “virtue”, is

solidarity. This then is not a feeling of vague compassion or shallow

distress at the misfortunes of so many people, both near and far. On

the contrary, it is a firm and persevering determination to commit

oneself to the common good; that is to say to the good of all and of

each individual, because we are all really responsible for all. (John

Paul II 1987: §V)

On this reading, the ground of solidarity is, as in Bourgeois and

Durkheim, an identification based on our role in the division of

labor, which includes a recognition that participation in an

unjust social order perpetuates suffering, and makes us accomplices.

The doctrine goes hand in hand with the Church’s teaching on

subsidiarity, in which local associations—including perhaps most

importantly the family—have ethical priority to more general,

encompassing associations, such as the state. More general and

encompassing organizing units should intervene in the affairs of the

lower only to help or aid them in the accomplishment of their tasks.

On this understanding, the response to individual suffering must be

collective; it cannot be done by individuals acting alone, but by each

body, at each level of generality, working together as a unit to

preserve the common good. As Pope Francis noted in a follow-up

catechism to his COVID19 encyclical Fratelli Tutti,

there is no true solidarity without social participation, without the

contribution of intermediary bodies: families, associations,

cooperatives, small businesses, and other expressions of society.

Everyone needs to contribute, everyone. (Francis

2020)[9]

2.5 Solidarity in social movements

In the late twentieth century, the predominant context in which

solidarity has had a place are modern social movements, such as

anticolonial, black, feminist, LGBTQ, and disabled struggles. It would

take us too far afield to review how solidarity is deployed in each

one of these movements. But it useful to give a sense of the kind of

questions that have motivated those engaged in them. One of the

central questions is the following: What should the basis of

the black, anticolonial, women’s movements, and so on, be?

Should, for example, the women’s movement be grounded in an idea

of sisterhood—on what unites women as women—or on

a commitment to the (feminist) cause (or both, or neither)? Should

black solidarity (for example in the US) be based in a shared

ethnocultural identity as a nation, or in common subjection to

oppression (or both, or neither)? Should Indigenous anti-colonial

movements in Canada be grounded in particular territorially-based

shared ways of life, or in broader commitments to overthrowing

European colonialism wherever it exists (or both, or neither)? (see,

e.g., Coulthard 2014; Simpson 2017). To give a sense of the debates,

we will focus on black solidarity and the idea of sisterhood.

Should solidarity among women as women be grounded in some

kind of shared experience of womanhood? It has become a staple of the

feminist literature that there is no shared experience of

simply being a woman. The attempt to identify a canonical list of

experiences that characterizes “being a woman” is likely

to lead to subtle forms of exclusion. Previous such attempts, it is

often argued, have reproduced the cis-gendered experiences of white,

middle-class women, and have marginalized the experiences of women

whose experiences do not fit on the list (Lorde 1984; Hill Collins

1990 [2000]; hooks 2000 [2015]; Combahee River Collective 1977/1983;

Spelman 1988). See also entry on

feminist perspectives on sex and gender.

The alternative to grounding sisterhood in shared experience or shared

oppression is to ground it in commitment to a cause or

coalition against patriarchy. The trouble with this view is

that it leaves open the question of how this defines a distinctive

form of sisterhood, rather than a form of feminist

solidarity. But is there anything distinctive about solidarity among

women as women? If so, what are its grounds?

One response is to ground sisterhood not in a shared

experience but in a shared condition of

oppression—where that condition is experienced in different ways

according to one’s overall structural position (which may be

further influenced by intersecting factors, such as race, class,

sexuality, and religion) (see, e.g., Young 1994).

This possible response to the challenge from exclusion invites a

further objection: if sisterhood is supposed to be grounded in a

shared condition defined by relations to a given set of socially

conditioned material objects (primarily the socially sexed body and

its reproductive functions), then doesn’t this also exclude? If

this is supposed to ground an identification among women as women,

then doesn’t sisterhood required constructing a shared narrative

regarding what these relations are how they condition the sexed body?

(Shrage 2009) But then doesn’t this just reinvite the challenge

from exclusion, since different women—depending on their

structural position—will find themselves subordinated and

oppressed by a different conglomeration of socially salient relations

and practices? Think, for example, of transgender women, or the

variety of ways in which race, sexuality, class, gender, and religion

intersect.[10]

Similar questions arise when considering the nature of Black

(American) solidarity. Should such solidarity be grounded in a shared

ethnocultural identity, in a shared condition as oppressed, in an

anti-racist cause as such, or in something else again (such as a

shared fate)? (These grounds are not, of course, exclusive: one might

believe that black solidarity should be grounded in both

ethnocultural identity and in the sense of sharing a distinct

condition of oppression.) An important strand of black

nationalism—one that was especially prominent in the1960s and

70s—holds that high-sounding appeals to the possibility of

integration in the name of a universal fight against injustice cannot

ground a robust solidarity among blacks. A deeper, widespread

engagement with a distinct culture is needed. According to this form

of nationalism, Black Americans (as descendants of slaves violently

abducted from Africa and elsewhere) constitute a distinct, and

distinctly cultural, nation-within-a-nation (Robinson 2001; Moses

1978). Nationalists argue that, though at the moment marginalized and

divided within itself, black culture calls for development and

expression (for example, in the arts, music, literature, and theatre)

(Cruse 1967); without it, and the sense of collective identity and

pride it secures, blacks cannot securely win their freedom in a

fundamentally hostile American society (see, e.g., Malcolm X 1970

[1992]; cf. Rivers 1995).

Many black liberals demur: while black cultural, economic, social,

cultural and political autonomy can be, in certain circumstances,

strategically useful in the fight against anti-black racism, it is

wrong-headed to insist on cultural unity as the basis of black

solidarity. Insisting on cultural unity is divisive and unnecessarily

exclusionary given the broad diversity of ethnic and social

backgrounds in the black community. Black solidarity should be

grounded, instead, on “thin” blackness, namely on shared

experiences of anti-black racism (see, e.g., Shelby 2005: 245; Hill

Collins 1990 [2000]; cf. Gooding-Williams 2009).

2.6 Conclusion

In this section, we have reviewed some of the salient histories in

which use of the term “solidarity” has figured. The survey

has had two functions. First, it has served to provide an overview of

the political and social uses for which solidarity has been enlisted.

Doing so enables us to frame the descriptive and normative challenges

that any theory of solidarity faces: Does solidarity have a single

nature that is repeated across different paradigmatic instances? Or is

it a malleable, vague term with no fixed content? What, if anything,

makes solidarity valuable? What should the grounds of solidarity be

in, for example, different social movements, in the welfare state, or

in political and social associations more broadly? Second, the survey

provides a testing ground for new theories of solidarity, which, we

have argued, should be responsive to the concept’s history.

Theories should be adopted and rejected according to whether they

successfully serve to describe, evaluate, and guide the various

practices in which the term figures, and has figured. While a theory

might recommend conceptual change, of course, it needs to be clear why

and how such a change is worth making. Either way, being aware of the

concept’s history is crucial since solidarity names not just an

ideal but a concrete set of practices.

3. The Value of Solidarity

It should be fairly uncontroversial that solidarity can have

instrumental value: when members of a marginalized group

develop bonds of solidarity by committing to each other and, as a

result of being in (or acting from) solidarity, they manage to

overcome their oppression, then solidarity has value because of its

causal/instrumental role. Similarly, it should not be controversial

that solidarity can have instrumental disvalue: even well-meaning,

morally justified acts undertaken in the spirit of solidarity can lead

to unforeseen and regrettable consequences. The more interesting and

challenging question is whether solidarity, as a social practice, also

has non-instrumental value (or disvalue). But before we move on to

this issue, let’s briefly list some of the instrumental values

that solidarity in different forms typically facilitates:

Most notably, solidarity improves a collective’s ability to

pursue projects. By committing to each other and experiencing unity,

fellows in solidarity establish a robust basis of mutual

identification that allows them to solve coordination issues and

pursue joint action that is more likely to succeed than if each acted

on their own (Shelby 2005). Groups that display solidarity also tend

to care for each other in beneficial ways, e.g., by protecting

vulnerable members or limiting social inequality amongst themselves

(Banting & Kymlicka 2017; Miller 2017). Beyond this, solidarity

has certain epistemic and relational benefits: whether as a result of

shared goals, shared experience, or shared oppression (see above),

fellows in solidarity consider each other trustworthy participants in

the pursuit of the common good, and they share information, jointly

deliberate and learn from each other about how to understand adversity

and oppression and pursue strategies to overcome it (Harvey 2007 on

epistemic solidarity; Goodin & Spiekermann 2015; Wiland 2017).

Does solidarity have value beyond these good consequences? Perhaps

some quick terminology is helpful. Non-instrumental value is value

that does not derive from making a contribution to something else.

Non-instrumental value is intrinsic if the value stems from

some (necessary?) internal property of the object (see: Intrinsic

vs. Extrinsic Value). Implicitly relying on such a notion of

intrinsic non-instrumental value, several authors have claimed that

solidarity’s value could only ever be instrumental. Rainer

Forst, for example, argues that solidarity could not be

“something intrinsically good, since a Mafia family

very much depends on the solidarity of its members”

(forthcoming) and he concludes that, therefore, solidarity is

“normatively dependent”. Other authors concur with this

judgment: solidarity is aimed at realizing justice or

overcoming oppression, and it is valuable when and because it realizes

this aim (Kohn forthcoming). The structure of the negative argument

here is clear enough:

If solidarity has non-instrumental value, then each

instance of it has value

Unity amongst mafia members is an instance of

solidarity

Unity amongst mafia members has no value

Therefore, solidarity has no non-instrumental

value.

Therefore, no internal property of solidarity

practices that is valuable as such, independent of the consequences

that it produces

There is, however, an interesting overlap here with an issue we

mentioned in

section 2,

namely whether or not solidarity ought to be moralized: according to

some authors that analyze such “pernicious solidarities”

as the one that prevails amongst mafia clans and white supremacists,

the correct response to Forst’s case is not to reject

that the idea that solidarity has non-instrumental value, but to deny

premise (2):

it is precisely for the reason that solidarity necessarily has some

good-making internal properties that we should not consider unity

amongst mafia members an instance of it.

It is not obvious how to resolve this potential disagreement. Is there

perhaps some other way to proceed? A better approach, we think, is

available if we scrutinize

premise (1):

Intrinsic value is just one way in which a practice could have

non-instrumental value. Whilst it may be true that a practice only has

intrinsic value if each instance of it has value, this is compatible

with its being non-instrumentally valuable in non-intrinsic ways. Here

are some important considerations: Only attributing instrumental value

to solidarity does, intuitively, seem to run up against at least two

kinds of cases. First, defenders of the non-instrumental value of

solidarity may point to the intuitive force of “futile

solidarity”: when the exploited workers come together to fight

for their rights in solidarity, we are likely to consider this

valuable even if their effort is ultimately thwarted. Second,

there is the very plausible thought that, somehow, a special kind of

value is realized when bad or unjust aspects of the world are brought

to an end through acts of solidarity: when the workers’ combined

agency causes the end of their oppression rather than, say, the

unexpected change of mind of their exploitative bosses, something

especially valuable has occurred.

Now of course there are things that defenders of the

“instrumental only” thesis can say in response: for

example, they may point out that there still are good consequences in

each of these examples, even if the overall goal has not been

realized. For example, there may be a sense of shared destiny or

reciprocal commitment amongst workers to each other that is

caused by solidarity. It is this reciprocal commitment (and

what it can lead to) that has value, not solidarity as such. The

problem with this response is that it seems to misdescribe the

relation between solidarity and whatever good has occurred in the

world. The reciprocal commitment that workers have towards each other,

for example, is not “caused” by solidarity: rather,

solidarity is partly or wholly constituted by it. One

suggestion, then, is that solidarity has non-instrumental value of a

non-intrinsic kind. What does this mean? The idea is that solidarity

is part-constitutive of something that is non-instrumentally valuable.

This allows for there to be some practice x that satisfies our

criteria for being solidaristic, and yet, it does not have value. But

it preserves the idea that solidarity is not only good for what it

causes but, if the right circumstances obtain, it is an integral

element in something that is intrinsically good.

There are at least two ways in which we might flesh out

solidarity’s non-instrumental value, one more individualistic

and one more collective. The more individualistic approach suggests

that we can understand solidarity’s non-instrumental value as

analogous to the value of other good dispositions and attitudes that

an agent can have. Specifically, philosophers thinking about the

goodness of virtue have argued that appropriately responding to

something that has value is itself something of (intrinsic) value, as

is negatively responding to something that has disvalue (Hurka 2001).

The connection to virtue works as follows: when an agent responds to

the adversity that they or others face by developing solidaristic

attitudes and dispositions—say by committing to ending

oppression with others picked out by the cause—then their having

these solidarist attitudes is non-instrumentally valuable because they

are negatively reacting to something that is of disvalue (oppression,

adversity etc.). But, and here is the rub, the agent’s response

is only valuable when it constitutes the correct

response to the relevant feature of the world. The white

supremacist’s solidarity is not valuable because the thing

against which his solidarity is directed, namely racial equality, is a

valuable state of affairs. But negatively responding to something that

has value clearly lacks non-instrumental value. This individualist

account of solidarity’s non-instrumental value is attractive

because it can account equally well for cases of “solidarity

amongst” and “solidarity with”. Moreover, it equally

applies to cases where agents privately develop the relevant

solidaristic attitudes without actually acting on them (e.g.,

discussed in Bommarito 2016; Zhao 2019; and Viehoff forthcoming).

Insofar as we think that their attitudes are valuable, some account

along these lines seems necessary to account for it.

But perhaps there is something missing from this individualistic

picture: one of the objections to those suggesting that solidarity

only has instrumental value relied on the idea that there is value in

people realizing a goal together. Shouldn’t our account

of solidarity’s non-instrumental value also be able to capture

this aspect? Recent literature has accounted for this in broadly two

ways (though these are not necessarily exclusive): Avery Kolers

maintains that, quite independently of pursuing justified aims,

solidarity groups constitute just (in his words

“equitable”) relations amongst participants. For Kolers,

in following the demands of solidarity and acting together,

we are not only working to (teleologically) bring about the end of

oppression; rather, we constitutively embody a non-oppressive

alternative world—even if, as is likely, our joint efforts

ultimately fail, in part or in whole. (Kolers 2016: 123–4)

So one way of highlighting non-instrumental collective value ensues

from focusing on the kind of community that relations of solidarity

give rise to: in acting together in the specific way required by the

ideal of solidarity, fellows already conform to norms of equity or

justice that they seek to bring about more widely.

Another line of argument is developed by Sangiovanni, who argues that,

when successfully pursuing valuable goals together, we create

non-instrumentally valuable joint agency:

We take pleasure in the exercise of those reciprocal, mutually

adjusted, and mutually reinforcing capabilities that have enabled us

to overcome forms of adversity that would have been impossible to

overcome alone. The collective activity of overcoming […] comes

to have non-instrumental value. (Sangiovanni forthcoming)

However, and similar to the more individualistic argument, the value

of jointly exercised agency is conditional: acting

successfully to overcome some obstacle is non-instrumentally valuable

only if the overcoming constitutes an achievement that is

worthwhile.

4. Challenges to Solidarity

Turning to criticisms of solidarity in this section, we start by

distinguishing different kinds of criticism along different

dimensions. Perhaps most importantly, one must distinguish between, on

the one hand, challenges to solidarity as a social practice (or a

range of social practices), and, on the other hand, criticism of

theories of solidarity. We will call criticisms of the former kind

“practical challenges” to solidarity and will address

those of the latter kind as “theoretical challenges”.

Practical and theoretical challenges are clearly independent of each

other. For example, one can think that we need a clear account of what

solidarity is, even if one holds that solidarity practices have, on

the whole, negative consequences for political life.

Theoretical challenges to solidarity can conceivably take

many forms, but we will focus here on the related charges of

conceptual incoherence and theoretical redundancy.

The former challenge is that uses of solidarity, both common sense and

philosophical, are simply too diffuse and incoherent to allow for any

adequate and theoretically productive definition. If those using the

concept of solidarity in political or philosophical debate are more

likely than not to misunderstand or speak past each other, then we

should not use the concept. The latter challenge is that, from a

theoretical standpoint, we don’t need to add solidarity to the

fundamental philosophical concepts in the discipline because we can

have everything we want by reflecting on alternative concepts and

theories that have already been more thoroughly developed, for example

justice, community, or equality.

When it comes to practical challenges to solidarity, critics

argue that solidarity tends to have negative consequences and that,

therefore, we should not promote it. We can further differentiate

these practical challenges in terms of, first, the kind of negative

consequences that are attributed to solidarity and, second, the kind

of solidarity practices that are judged to be vulnerable to this

challenge. In relation to the former, the most prominent criticisms

concern solidarity’s impact on the realization of other

important social and political values. One historically important line

of criticism to solidarity argues that solidarity threatens

liberty (Arendt, Shklar, Kateb). Others worry that solidarity

creates unfair forms of inequality between those within a solidary

group and those who are excluded (Scheffler 2001). Whilst the

criticism focus on negative effects on outsiders, critics have also

argued that solidarity may have negative effects on participants.

Perhaps most notably, some have claimed that solidarity stymies

pluralism and diversity. A related but distinct

worry is that solidarity promotes—or perhaps even

requires—false beliefs and self-conceptions amongst participants

(Margalit 2017; Shelby forthcoming).

Before we move on to specific arguments, a point about generality: We

maintain that, for a criticism to amount to a “challenge”

to solidarity, it must rise to a certain level of generality, i.e., it

must apply to a range of accounts of solidarity.

4.1 Theoretical criticism of solidarity

Since we are here interested in theoretical challenges to

solidarity (and not just objections to particular accounts),

we focus on challenges that, if true, would undermine the very

endeavor of elevating solidarity’s place amongst significant

theoretical concepts in the discipline.

4.1.1 Conceptual incoherence

A first theoretical worry about solidarity is that, given the

diversity of linguistic usage, the range of contexts of application,

and the breadth of phenomena addressed in the philosophical literature

under the label, solidarity is conceptually incoherent. How might this

be the case? To use a somewhat far-fetched example, imagine that we

were charged with developing an account of the descriptive features,

goodness or permissibility of all human activities that start with the

letter “L”. Because the actions picked out by our category

are simply too heterogeneous (there is nothing interesting that

laughing and lying, let alone loving and lynching have in common), any

theorizing would be pointless. Could it be the case that

“solidarity” picks out a set of actions and practices that

are simply too heterogeneous to lead to anything theoretically

insightful? Niklas Luhmann, for example, suggested that solidarity is

obsolete, a mere “formula of ideology” without determinate

content (Luhmann [1984] quoted in Thome 1999: 101).

Despite the initial plausibility of this objection to theorizing

solidarity, we think that solidarity theorists have powerful responses

available. First, they can point to similarities that unify the

descriptive, normative and evaluative features of instantiations of

solidarity, even those as diverse as those mentioned above. For

example, different authors have sought to show that despite their

initial heterogeneity, solidarity in all these contexts descriptively

entails a form of identification, or a sentiment of unity, or some

orientation towards overcoming an obstacle or adversity, or some

combination of these elements (Scholz 2008; Taylor 2015; Prainsack

& Buyx 2017). Moreover, authors have subcategorized solidarity

along social contexts—political solidarity, civic

solidarity—(Bayertz 1999a; Scholz 2008), thereby organizing our

heterogeneous linguistic use to allow for useful theoretical

approaches to more determinate social practices of

solidarity. Finally, theorists of solidarity can respond that, in

providing a theoretical/philosophical account of solidarity, there is

some freedom to make revisionary proposals about what should

count as solidarity. Our (descriptive, normative, evaluative)

understanding of solidarity is advanced if we “sharpen”

our account of solidarity by excluding some peripheral uses, then that

may well be legitimate and will limit the charge of

incoherence. Theorists of solidarity may also point to other social

and political concepts to claim that heterogeneous use both in

everyday discourse and among philosophers is rarely considered a

convincing reason to abstain from theorizing concepts like freedom,

equality, justice, and the like. Why treat solidarity differently?

4.1.2 Theoretical redundancy

Faced with this appeal to other political concepts, critics may

retreat to a related but distinct criticism: They may accept that

concepts like freedom and equality too are beset with complexity and

conceptual disagreements that need to be resolved. But they can then

insist that there is no need to take up this difficult endeavor for

solidarity because—contrary to liberty, equality

etc.—there is no need for a theory of solidarity. This is the

charge of theoretical redundancy: we can gain exactly the

same explanatory mileage by using existing concepts and categories

without theorizing solidarity. Descriptively, existing work

on altruism, community and relations of loyalty might serve us just as

well as accounts of solidarity: all of the relations that were

described as solidaristic above are also (more or less intimate)

communal relations amongst people. Normatively, the critic

might suggest that we can reduce the claims generated by solidarity to

requirements of justice, fairness, equality, and the like. And

evaluatively, we can appeal to the general goodness of

special bonds and relationships for the realization of a flourishing

life, whether they are bonds of friendship, family, religion, or

political community. If this were the case, then theorizing solidarity

would be redundant, and ultimately, pointless. Why not, in a spirit of

parsimony, simply rely on the concepts and theories we already

have?

Again, we think that defenders of solidarity have good replies

available: Perhaps the strongest response to the challenge of

redundancy is to provide a substantive account of solidarity in terms

of its distinctive descriptive, normative and evaluative features. If

such an account is illuminating, then the charge of redundancy seems

beside the point. More specifically, theorists of solidarity can

appeal to distinctive descriptive or positive features of

solidarity practices that make it inappropriate to subsume solidarity

under a generic account of community and loyalty (see discussion in

Kolers 2016: chapter 2). Unlike those bonds of friendship and family,

for example, solidarity is purposive (goal-oriented), both in the

sense that solidarity aims for the achievement of overcoming some

obstacle or adversity and in the sense that fellows are picked de

dicto in terms of the cause that is pursued rather than in some

goal-independent manner (Arnsperger & Varoufakis 2003; Kolers

2016). In terms of normative distinctiveness, theorists of solidarity

may also object to the critic’s implied assumption that a

theoretical account of x’s normative properties loses its

usefulness when we discover that these properties supervene on or are

explained by a more general moral consideration.

4.2 Practical challenges to Solidarity

We now move on to the practical challenges of solidarity. Should we be

critical of real-world solidarity practices because they lead to bad

consequences? Or may there perhaps even be something constitutively

problematic about solidarity movements? Three prominent objections

relate to solidarity’s impact on liberty, fairness, and

truth.

4.2.1 Does solidarity threaten liberty?

Does solidarity muffle liberty? In her celebrated essay the

“Liberalism of Fear”, Judith Shklar claims it does. She

writes:

We must therefore be suspicious of ideologies of solidarity, precisely

because they are so attractive to those who find liberalism

emotionally unsatisfying, and who have gone on in our century to

create oppressive and cruel regimes of unparalleled horror. […]

To seek emotional and personal development in the bosom of a community

or in romantic self-expression is a choice open to citizens in liberal

societies. Both, however, are apolitical impulses and wholly

self-oriented, which at best distract us from the main task of

politics when they are presented as political doctrines, and at worst

can, under unfortunate circumstances, seriously damage liberal

practices. For although both appear only to be redrawing the

boundaries between the personal and the public […] it cannot be

said that either one has a serious sense of the implications of the

proposed shifts in either direction. (Shklar 1989: 36)

There is, one might think, an element of truth here: theorists of

solidarity tend to emphasize that solidarity becomes important when

and because we sense the need for collective resistance and unity of

purpose in the face of adversity. They also stress the

non-instrumental value in setting aside self-interest in a horizontal

identification with others on behalf of a shared goal, where part of

what is valued is our seeing, together, our collective agency

reflected in the ends we pursue (see previous section).

The element of identification may seem particularly problematic.

Identification requires, among other things, coming to see others as

“like oneself”, and taking that similarity as a basis for

joint concern, empathy, and normative orientation. So, for example,

when I identify with you as a worker, I see our common role

as providing an important orientation in my life. In this sense,

solidarity demands that one set aside the personal for the political

(thus “redrawing the boundaries” between them). The worry

is that, at least in politics, solidarity’s demand for

similarity, commitment, and loyalty leads to unfreedom and

tyranny.[11]

Faced with this fundamental challenge, theorists of solidarity have at

least two arguments: First, they may insist that it is false to treat

a commitment to solidarity as incompatible with a commitment to

liberalism. To be sure, solidarities organized to promote illiberal

ends by illiberal means are, well, illiberal by definition. But their

disregard for individual rights or freedom or equality is not entailed

or required by their solidarity. Indeed, if, as Shklar and others

emphasize, liberalism demands vigilance, hatred of injustice, and a

readiness to resist power when necessary, then liberalism requires

solidarity. Resistance is most effective when it is conducted by

groups whose grievances are shared and known to be shared.

These grievances provide a spring for joint action, and a powerful

source of identification. Such identification is necessary to overcome

fear, and it allows people to act pro-socially by looking beyond their

immediate self-interest to the larger task at hand.

A second reason why these challenges are not fully convincing is this:

In Shklar the target is what we might call state-level

solidarity. Though they do not name it, their target is national or

patriotic solidarity—solidarity as invoked by those who have

political power and who aim to rally the people against an enemy, or

solidarity as it is invoked by those who believe that active, partisan

political participation is essential for a flourishing life. The first

response is simply to point out (as this entry does) that solidarity

can be at the heart of social movements and bottom-up political

action. It need not be solely focused on or through the state. The

second response is that even state-level solidarity need not be so

pernicious. Civic solidarity need not enforce blind conformity,

disrespect difference or disagreement, or raze

plurality.[12]

There is a rich tradition in the history of political

ideas—stretching from Leon

Bourgeois’[13]

solidarism to present writings—that grounds civic solidarity

not in some “totalizing” pre-political identity, but in

the mutual interdependence of citizens and their democratic

co-authorship of justice-preserving

institutions.[14]

4.2.2 Does solidarity promote false beliefs?

Solidarity, it was said, imposes not only demands on what to do but

also on what fellows should believe. With regard to such beliefs,

solidarity requires fellows to see each other as united by some common

feature, or condition or experience. Does solidarity systematically

lead to false beliefs amongst members of solidarity groups, for

example about what unites them?

Perhaps most prominently, the question of the relationship

between—in this case, historical—truth and the

kind of collective group identification necessary for solidarity has

come up in debates about (liberal) nationalism. Here, the charge

against nationalist solidarity is that, for essentially instrumental

purposes, national identity both relies on and promotes false beliefs

amongst members about some glorified national past (Abizadeh 2004).

Other forms of solidarity need not, of course, rely on some shared

historical origins amongst participants. But the challenge can be

generalized: insofar as solidarity requires some ground for mutual

identification, whether shared experience, shared oppression, or

shared goals, there is a danger that the practice systematically

guides participants to overestimate those identification-grounding

features at the expense of other, perhaps more salient, elements that

are not shared amongst them. To go back to two earlier examples,

sisterhood may require participants to see some feature of their

identity (“being a woman”) as particularly important when,

in fact, their de facto situation of social disadvantage is (also)

fundamentally structured by other categories like race or class.

Similarly, black solidarity asks participants to focus on whatever

grounds commonality amongst blacks, even if their actual social

position is shaped by matters of class, gender, migration status, and

so on (Shelby forthcoming).

Confronted with the fact that much of what is promulgated as part of

shared national history does not hold up against the historical

record, liberal nationalists like David Miller (1995) have responded

that “myths” about a national collective’s past need

not be true so long as they serve the purpose of supporting those

attitudes that underpin valuable national solidarity. But irrespective

of whether or not they are useful, they are untrue,

and, to the extent that the group identification necessary for

national solidarity depends on it, it depends on having false

beliefs.

Does this worry generalize to all forms of solidarity? One important

difference between national solidarity and other forms is that most

other solidarities do not typically depend on beliefs in something

that is manifestly untrue. Rather, they emphasize the relevance of

some genuine aspect of a person’s practical

identity—whether it is shared experience, shared oppression,

shared goals etc.—over others. We might add that whether or not

some feature is salient for one’s practical identity

is, at least to a degree, up to the relevant agent. So one

conciliatory response that defenders of (non-national) solidarity

might offer is that solidarity does not depend on belief in

falsehoods, but rather that it expresses which aspects of their

identity participants take to be important. They might add that,

insofar as there is free deliberation both about what unites and,

importantly, what divides participants to solidarity movements, the

charge of promoting false beliefs is beside the point. In a more

combative vein, they may also add that, at least in some cases,

solidarity is actually a necessary element for the formation of

correct beliefs about one’s own and others’ predicament.

Wiland describes this as epistemic solidarity (Wiland 2017:

69). Thus, standing in solidarity with others that have suffered from

similar instances of adversity and oppression can be a necessary

condition for enabling each other to make sense of our predicament: We

form true beliefs about our shared predicament and improve our ability

to define and fight oppressive conditions by being able to trust each

other’s oppression-related testimony (Goodin & Spiekermann

2015).

4.2.3 Is solidarity exclusionary / unfair towards outsiders?

Whatever else solidarity entails descriptively; it entails a special

commitment to one’s solidarity fellows that one does not hold

towards everybody else. And whatever normative consequences solidarity

has for those in solidarity, it will ground some special

claims that these fellows have on us and we on them. In this sense,

solidarity, like friendship, family, and nationality, constitutes a

special relationship with special obligations. Over recent decades, a

number of philosophers have raised challenges to the very idea that

special obligations can be justified towards those who are not part of

them. Perhaps most prominently, Samuel Scheffler has raised a

fairness-based “distributive objection” to all special

relationships (Scheffler 2001). If fellows in solidarity form special

relationships with special obligations, then, does Scheffler’s

criticism apply here too?

The distributive objection builds on the idea that participants to

special relationships receive special benefits from each other: qua

membership, we are owed not just more from fellow participants than we

are from outsiders, but we are also owed priority, in at least some

instances. What the distributive objection observes is that members

already benefit from the relationship goods that are constitutively

tied to being in a meaningful relationship. The problem is that, then,

fellows also owe less to outsiders then they did beforehand: Special

relationships—including solidarity relations—thus

function, to use Scheffler’s memorable phrase, like “moral

tax shelters” to those who already benefit.

Whilst several authors have rejected the general thrust of the

distributive objection (Kolodny 2002; Lazar 2009), we want to point to

some features of solidarity that should provide specific cover against

this challenge. Crucially, friends of solidarity may stress that

unlike friendship or love relations, solidarity obligations are not

necessarily grounded in the value of the relationship, but in

relationship-independent value that comes from having these duties.

Special duties of solidarity would then be justified more like role

obligations—lawyers, for example, have fiduciary duties to

represent their client’s interests not because of the

non-instrumental value of lawyer-client relationships, but because of

the advantages that vesting them with such duties has for the

system’s overall ability to optimally realize impartial moral

demands (such as protecting innocent defendants). On this strategy,

duties of solidarity would ultimately be grounded in non-partial

values like fairness and natural justice. How might this justification

run? Many of our positive general duties are imperfect, so that even

well-meaning people are likely to face significant obstacles in

discharging them: it requires the ability to coordinate our actions in

complex ways with others; and we must also be motivated to make

contributions in light of other important projects and relationships.

If the special obligations that flow from solidarity commitments can

provide us with a robust way of solving issues of coordination and

motivation (because, following a solidarity-commitment, discharging

our general duties through solidarity somehow better aligns with our

personal projects) then those obligations could be justified by an

appeal to impartial moral considerations (Kolers 2016; Viehoff

forthcoming).

But even for those who think that some duties of solidarity

are grounded in the non-instrumental value of solidaristic fellowship,

there are important responses available: First, solidarity (at least

in its most paradigmatic forms) establishes unity amongst those

suffering from injustice or oppression, so it rather far from

providing some kind of indirect protection from more extensive duties

towards the more vulnerable. Second, special responsibilities towards

our fellows, like other special duties, are not absolute: very

plausibly, they are constrained by general demands of justice. So even

if special obligations among fellows in solidarity could ground some

partiality, these duties would be limited by more weighty

considerations of justice.

Do these responses answer all the possible objections of fairness and

exclusion? Probably not; questions of permissible solidaristic

partiality, especially amongst large-scale collectives like the state,

clearly depend on questions of social and global justice that cannot

be addressed here. So questions of the kinds of obligations that

solidarity practices can ground blend into issues of justice. But that

should not be surprising, nor should it prevent us from reflection on

solidarity in its own right.

Bibliography

Abizadeh, Arash, 2004, “Historical Truth, National Myths and

Liberal Democracy: On the Coherence of Liberal Nationalism”,

Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3): 291–313.

doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00201.x

Appiah, Anthony, 1985, “The Uncompleted Argument: Du Bois

and the Illusion of Race”, Critical Inquiry, 12(1):

21–37. doi:10.1086/448319

Arendt, Hannah, 1963, On Revolution, New York: Viking

Press.

–––, 1951 [1973], The Origins of

Totalitarianism, New York: Harcourt, Brace. New edition, New

York: Harcourt Brace & Jovanovich, 1973.

Arnsperger, Christian and Yanis Varoufakis, 2003, “Toward a

Theory of Solidarity”, Erkenntnis, 59(2):

157–188. doi:10.1023/A:1024630228818

Banting, Keith and Will Kymlicka (eds.), 2017, The Strains of

Commitment: The Political Sources of Solidarity in Diverse

Societies, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198795452.001.0001

Bayertz, Kurt, 1999a, “Four Uses of

‘Solidarity’”, in Bayertz 1999b:3–28.

doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9245-1_1

––– (ed.), 1999b, Solidarity,

(Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture), Dordrecht: Springer

Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9245-1

Blais, Marie-Claude, 2007, La solidarité: histoire

d’une idée, (Bibliothèque des idées),

Paris: Gallimard.

Bommarito, Nicolas, 2016, “Private Solidarity”,

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19(2): 445–455.

doi:10.1007/s10677-015-9640-2

Bourgeois, M. Léon, 1902, “Rapport de M. Léon

Bourgeois au Congrès d’Éducation Sociale en

1900”, in Solidarité, 3rd edition, by

M. Léon Bourgeois, Paris: Armand Colin, 159–188. [First

edition published in 1896.]

Bowles, Samuel and Herbert Gintis, 2011, “A Cooperative

Species”, in their A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity

and Its Evolution, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,

1–7.

Bratman, Michael, 2014, Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of

Acting Together, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199897933.001.0001

Carastathis, Anna, 2014, “The Concept of Intersectionality

in Feminist Theory”, Philosophy Compass, 9(5):

304–314. doi:10.1111/phc3.12129

Claeys, Gregory, 2011, “Non-Marxian Socialism

1815–1914”, in The Cambridge History of

Nineteenth-Century Political Thought, Gareth Stedman Jones and

Gregory Claeys (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

521–555. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521430562.018

Clark, Meghan J., 2014, The Vision of Catholic Social Thought:

The Virtue of Solidarity and the Praxis of Human Rights,

Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.

Combahee River Collective, 1977/1983, “A Black Feminist

Statement”, April 1977, Boston, MA. Printed in Home Girls: A

Black Feminist Anthology, Barbara Smith (ed.), New York: Kitchen

Table—Women of Color Press, 1983. New edition, New Brunswick,

NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2000, 264–274.

Coulthard, Glen Sean, 2014, Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting

the Colonial Politics of Recognition, (Indigenous Americas),

Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

Crenshaw, Kimberle, 1991, “Mapping the Margins:

Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence against Women of

Color”, Stanford Law Review, 43(6): 1241–1299.

doi:10.2307/1229039

Cruse, Harold, 1967, The Crisis of the Negro Intellectual: A

Historical Analysis of the Failure of Black Leadership, New York:

William Morrow.

Dawson, Michael C., 2001, Black Visions: The Roots of

Contemporary African-American Political Ideologies, Chicago:

University of Chicago Press.

Dean, Jodi, 1995, “Reflective Solidarity”,

Constellations, 2(1): 114–140.

doi:10.1111/j.1467-8675.1995.tb00023.x

Deveaux, Monique, 2021, Poverty, Solidarity, and Poor-Led

Social Movements, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/oso/9780190850289.001.0001

Durkheim, Émile, 1928 [1959], Le socialisme: sa

définition, ses débuts, la doctrine

Saint-Simonienne, Marcel Mauss (ed.), (Travaux de

l’Année sociologique), Paris: F. Alcan. Translated as

Socialism and Saint-Simon, Charlotte Sattler (trans.), Yellow

Springs, OH: Antioch Press, 1959.

–––, 1893 [1984], De la division du travail

social, Paris: Félix Alcan; second edition 1902, third

edition 1911. Translated as The Division of Labor in Society,

W. D. Halls (trans.), New York: Free Press.

Dworkin, Ronald, 2011, Justice for Hedgehogs, Cambridge,

MA: Harvard University Press.

Engels, Friedrich, 1876 [1978], Herrn Eugen Dühring's

Umwälzung der Wissenschaft, a translated abstract of which

was published as “Socialism: Utopian and Scientific” and

collected in Tucker 1978, pp. 683–718.

Faucci, Riccardo and Antonella Rancan, 2009, “Transforming

the Economy: Saint-Simon and His Influence on Mazzini”,

History of Economic Ideas, 17(2): 79–105.

Feinberg, Joel, 1973, Social Philosophy, (Foundations of

Philosophy Series), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Forst, Rainer, forthcoming, “Contexts of Solidarity”,

in Sangiovanni and Viehoff forthcoming.

Francis, 2020, “Catechesis ‘Healing the world’:

8. Subsidiarity and virtue of hope”, 23 September 2020.

[Francis 2020 available online]

Fricker, Miranda, 2007, Epistemic Injustice: Power and the

Ethics of Knowing, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198237907.001.0001

Garton Ash, Timothy, 1983 [2002], The Polish Revolution:

Solidarity, London: J. Cape. Third edition, New Haven, CT: Yale

University Press, 2002.

Goodin, Robert E. and Kai Spiekermann, 2015, “Epistemic

Solidarity as a Political Strategy”, Episteme, 12(4):

439–457. doi:10.1017/epi.2015.29

Gooding-Williams, Robert, 2009, In the Shadow of Du Bois:

Afro-Modern Political Thought in America, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Gould, Carol C., 2007, “Transnational Solidarities”,

Journal of Social Philosophy, 38(1): 148–164.

doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00371.x

–––, 2020, “Motivating Solidarity with

Distant Others: Empathic Politics, Responsibility, and the Problem of

Global Justice”, in The Oxford Handbook of Global

Justice, Thom Brooks (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press,

121–138. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198714354.013.6

–––, forthcoming, “Rethinking Solidarity

through the Lens of Critical Social Ontology”, in Sangiovanni

and Viehoff forthcoming.

Glasgow, Joshua, 2009, A Theory of Race, New York:

Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203880951

Harvey, Jean, 2007, “Moral Solidarity and Empathetic

Understanding: The Moral Value and Scope of the Relationship”,

Journal of Social Philosophy, 38(1): 22–37.

doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00364.x

Hayward, J. E. S., 1959, “Solidarity: The Social History of

an Idea in Nineteenth Century France”, International Review

of Social History, 4(2): 261–284.

doi:10.1017/S0020859000001371

Hechter, Michael, 2015, “Solidarity, Sociology of”, in

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral

Sciences, second edition, James D. Wright (ed.), Oxford:

Elsevier, 6–9. doi:10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.32147-X

Hill Collins, Patricia, 1990 [2000], Black Feminist Thought:

Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment,

(Perspectives on Gender 2), Boston: Unwin Hyman. Second edition, New

York: Routledge, 2000. doi:10.4324/9780203900055

hooks, bell, 1981 [2015], Ain’t I a Woman, London:

Routledge. [First edition published 1981, second edition 2015.]

–––, 2000 [2015], Feminism Is for Everybody:

Passionate Politics, Cambridge, MA: South End Press. Second

edition, New York: Routledge, 2015.

Hurka, Thomas, 2001, Virtue, Vice, and Value, New York:

Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195137167.001.0001

John Paul II, 1987, Sollicitudo rei socialis, 20 December

1987

[Sollicitudo rei socialis available online (English)]

Kateb, George, 1989, “Democratic Individuality and the

Meaning of Rights”, in Rosenblum 1989: 183–206 (ch. 10).

doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674864443.c14

Kautsky, Karl, 1892 [1910], The Class Struggle: Erfurt

Program, trans. William Bohn, New York: Kerr & Co.

[Originally published as Das Erfurter Programm in seinem

grundsätzlichen Theil erläutert, Stuttgart:

Vorwärts.

Kohn, M., (forthcoming), “Solidarity: The Link Between Facts

and Norms”, in The Virtue of Solidarity, Andrea

Sangiovanni and Juri Viehoff (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University

Press.

Kolers, Avery, 2016, A Moral Theory of Solidarity,

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198769781.001.0001

Kolodny, Niko, 2002, “Do Associative Duties Matter?”,

Journal of Political Philosophy, 10(3): 250–266.

doi:10.1111/1467-9760.00152

Koslowski, Peter, 2000, “Solidarism, Capitalism, and

Economic Ethics in Heinrich Pesch”, in The Theory of

Capitalism in the German Economic Tradition: Historism,

Ordo-Liberalism, Critical Theory, Solidarism, Peter Koslowski

(ed.), (Studies in Economic Ethics and Philosophy), Berlin/Heidelberg:

Springer, 371–396. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-04084-3_10

Land, Clare, 2015, Decolonizing Solidarity: Dilemmas and

Directions for Supporters of Indigenous Struggles, London: Zed

Books.

Lazar, Seth, 2009, “Debate: Do Associative Duties Really Not

Matter? 1”, Journal of Political Philosophy, 17(1):

90–101. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00329.x

Leo XIII, 1891, Rerum Novarum.

[Rerum Navarum available online (English)]

Leopold, David, 2015, “Scientific Socialism: The Case of

Robert Owen”, in Scientific Statesmanship, Governance and

the History of Political Philosophy, Kyriakos N. Demetriou and

Antis Loizides (eds.), New York: Routledge, 193–209.

Leroux, Pierre, 1840 [1845], De l’humanité: de

son principe, et de son avenir, où. se trouve exposée la

vraie définition de la religion et où l’on

explique le sens, la suite, et l’enchaînement du Mosaisme

et du Christianisme, Paris: Perrotin. Second edition 1845.

Lorde, Audre, 1984, Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches,

(Crossing Press Feminist Series), Freedom, CA: Crossing Press.

Luhmann, Niklas, 1984, “Die Differenzierung von Interaktion

und Gesellschaft. Probleme der sozialen Solidarität”, in

Solidarität in der Welt der 80er Jahre: Leistungsgesellschaft

und Sozialstaat, Robert Kopp (ed.), Basel: Helbing and

Lichtenhahn, 79–96.

Malcolm X, 1970 [1992], By Any Means Necessary, New York:

Pathfinder. Second edition, 1992.

Margalit, Avishai, 2017, On Betrayal, Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press.

Marx, Karl, 1871 [1978], Speech, 8 September 1872 in Amsterdam

after a congress of the First International. Collected as “The

possibility of non-violent revolution (the Amsterdam speech)” in

Tucker 1978, pp. 522–525.

Mason, Andrew, 2000, Community, Solidarity, and Belonging:

Levels of Community and Their Normative Significance,

Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490309

May, Larry, 1996, The Socially Responsive Self: Social Theory

and Professional Ethics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago

Press.

Mazzini, Giuseppe, 1871 [2009], “Nazionalismo e

Nazionalità”. Translated as “Nationalism and

Nationality”, in A Cosmopolitanism of Nations: Giuseppe

Mazzini’s Writings on Democracy, Nation Building, and

International Relations, Stefano Recchia and Nadia Urbinati

(eds.), Stefano Recchia (trans.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

Press, 2009, 62–65.

Medina, José, 2013, The Epistemology of Resistance:

Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant

Imaginations, (Studies in Feminist Philosophy), Oxford/New York:

Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199929023.001.0001

Michnik, Adam, 1985, “Letter from Gdansk Prison”,

Jerzy B. Warman (trans.), The New York Review of Books, 18

July 1985.

Miller, David, 1995, On Nationality, (Oxford Political

Theory), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

–––, 2017, “Solidarity and Its

Sources”, in Banting and Kymlicka 2017: 61–79 (ch. 2).

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198795452.003.0002

Mohanty, Chandra Talpade, 2003, Feminism without Borders:

Decolonizing Theory, Practicing Solidarity, Durham, NC: Duke

University Press.

Moses, Wilson Jeremiah, 1978, The Golden Age of Black

Nationalism, 1850–1925, Hamden, CT: Archon Books.

O’Neill, Onora, 1996, Towards Justice and Virtue: A

Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning, Cambridge/New York:

Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511621239

Owen, Robert, 1826–27 [2016], “The Social

System”, The New-Harmony Gazette, volume 2, several

issues. Reprinted in Selected Works of Robert Owen, Gregory

Claeys (ed.), (The Pickering Masters), London: W. Pickering, 1993.

Reprinted, New York: Routledge, 2016, volume 2, 56–105.

Pesch, Heinrich, 1918 [2004], Ethik und Volkswirtschaft,

Freiburg im Breisgau: Herdersche verlagshandlung. Translated as

Ethics and the National Economy, Rupert J. Ederer (trans.),

Norfolk, VA: IHS Press, 2004.

Plunkett, David and Tim Sundell, 2013, “Disagreement and the

Semantics of Normative and Evaluative Terms”,

Philosopher’s Imprint, 13: article 23.

[Plunkett and Sundell 2013 available online]

Potter, Mark W., 2009, “Solidarity as Spiritual Exercise: A

Contribution to the Development of Solidarity in the Catholic Social

Tradition”, PhD thesis, Boston College.

[Potter 2009 available online]

Prainsack, Barbara and Alena Buyx, 2017, Solidarity in

Biomedicine and Beyond, (Cambridge Bioethics and Law 33),

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781139696593

Renan, Ernest, 1882, Qu’est que c’est qu’une

nation, Paris: Calmann-Lévy. [Quoted translation is by the

authors.]

Renaud, Hippolyte, 1842, Solidarité: Vue

Synthétique sur la Doctrine de Charles Fourier, Paris:

Librairie de l’École Sociétaire; second edition

1845, third edition 1846.

Rivers, Eugene F., 1995, “Beyond the Nationalism of Fools:

Toward an Agenda for Black Intellectuals”, Boston

Review, 20(3/Summer): 16–18.

Robinson, Dean E., 2001, Black Nationalism in American

Politics and Thought, New York: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511606038

Rosenblum, Nancy L. (ed.), 1989, Liberalism and the Moral

Life, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674864443

Sangiovanni, Andrea, forthcoming, Solidarity: Its Nature,

Grounds, and Value, Manchester: Manchester University Press.

Sangiovanni, Andrea and Juri Viehoff (eds), forthcoming,

Solidarity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Scheffler, Samuel, 2001, Boundaries and Allegiances: Problems

of Justice and Responsibility in Liberal Thought, Oxford/New

York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199257671.001.0001

Scholz, Sally J., 2008, Political Solidarity, University

Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Sewell, William H., 1980, Work and Revolution in France: The

Language of Labor from the Old Regime to 1848, Cambridge/New

York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511583711

Shelby, Tommie, 2005, We Who Are Dark: The Philosophical

Foundations of Black Solidarity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press. doi:10.4159/9780674043527

–––, forthcoming, “A Tale of Two Tenths:

Race, Class, and Solidarity”, in Sangiovanni and Viehoff

forthcoming.

Shklar, Judith N., 1989, “The Liberalism of Fear”, in

Rosenblum 1989: 21–38 (ch. 1).

doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674864443.c2

Shrage, Laurie (ed.), 2009, “You’ve

Changed”: Sex Reassignment and Personal Identity, (Studies

in Feminist Philosophy), Oxford/New York: Oxford University

Press.

Simpson, Leanne Betasamosake, 2017, As We Have Always Done:

Indigenous Freedom through Radical Resistance, (Indigenous

Americas), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

Spelman, Elizabeth V., 1988, Inessential Woman: Problems of

Exclusion in Feminist Thought, Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

Tajfel, Henri and John Turner, 2001, “An Integrative Theory

of Intergroup Conflict”, in Intergroup Relations: Essential

Readings, Michael A. Hogg and Dominic Abrams (eds.), (Key

Readings in Social Psychology), New York: Psychology Press,

94–109.

Tajfel, Henri, M. G. Billig, R. P. Bundy, and Claude Flament,

1971, “Social Categorization and Intergroup Behaviour”,

European Journal of Social Psychology, 1(2): 149–178.

doi:10.1002/ejsp.2420010202

Taylor, A., 2015, ‘Solidarity: Obligations and

Expressions’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 23:

128–45.

Taylor, Charles, 1989, “Cross-Purposes: The

Liberal-Communitarian Debate”, in Rosenblum 1989: 159–182

(ch. 9). doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674864443.c13

Thome, Helmut, 1999, “Solidarity: Theoretical Perspectives

for Empirical Research”, in Bayertz 1999b: 101–131.

doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9245-1_6

Tischner, Józef, 1982 [1984], Etyka

solidarności, Paris: Spotkania. 2nd Ed. Translated as

The Spirit of Solidarity, Marek B. Zaleski and Benjamin Fiore

(trans.), San Francisco: Harper & Row.

Tucker, R. C. (ed.), 1978, The Marx-Engels Reader,

London: Norton.

Van Parijs, Philippe, forthcoming, “Solidarity and the Just

Society”, in Sangiovanni and Viehoff forthcoming.

Viehoff, Juri, forthcoming, “Personal Sacrifice, Commitment,

and the Value of Solidarity”, in Sangiovanni and Viehoff

forthcoming.

Wiland, Eric, 2017, “Moral Testimony: Going on the

Offensive”, in Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12, Russ

Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1:chapter 3.

Wildt, Andreas, 1999, “Solidarity: Its History and

Contemporary Definition”, in Bayertz 1999b: 209–220.

doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9245-1_11

Young, Iris Marion, 1994, “Gender as Seriality: Thinking

about Women as a Social Collective”, Signs, 19(3):

713–738.

Zakaria, Rafia, 2021, Against White Feminism: Notes on

Disruption, New York: W.W. Norton.

Zhao, Michael, 2019, “Solidarity, Fate-Sharing, and

Community”, Philosopher’s Imprint, 19: article

46.

[Zhao 2019 available online]

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.

Preview the PDF version of this entry

at the

Friends of the SEP Society.

Look up this entry topic

at the

Internet Philosophy Ontology Project

(InPhO).

Enhanced bibliography for this entry

at

PhilPapers,

with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries

citizenship |

common good |

feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on sex and gender |

nationalism |

responsibility: collective |

socialism

Copyright © 2023 by

Andrea Sangiovanni

Juri Viehoff

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.

The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support

Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Accessibility

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Mirror Sites

View this site from another server:

USA (Main Site)

Philosophy, Stanford University

Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Just a moment...

a moment...Enable JavaScript and cookies to conti

solidarity是什么意思_solidarity怎么读_solidarity翻译_用法_发音_词组_同反义词_团结-新东方在线英语词典

solidarity是什么意思_solidarity怎么读_solidarity翻译_用法_发音_词组_同反义词_团结-新东方在线英语词典

英语词典 -

日语词典

首页 > 英语词典 > 字母单词表 > s开头的单词 > solidarity

solidarity

听听怎么读

英 [ˌsɒlɪˈdærəti]

美 [ˌsɑlɪˈdærəti]

是什么意思

n.团结;

变形

复数:solidarities

双语释义

n.(名词)[U] 团结 unity resulting from common interests or feelings

英英释义

solidarity[ ,sɔli'dæriti ]n.a union of interests or purposes or sympathies among members of a group

学习怎么用

双语例句

用作名词(n.)Their sense of solidarity is very low.他们的团结观念非常薄弱。The strike fostered a sense of solidarity among the workers.罢工促进了工人之间的团结。

权威例句

Human Development Report 2007/2008. Fighting climate change: human solidarity in a divided world.Fighting climate change: human solidarity in a ...Fighting climate change : human solidarity in a divided worldHDR 2007/2008 - Fighting climate change: Human solidarity in a divided worldFeminism without Borders: Decolonizing Theory, Practicing Solidarity by Chandra Talpade MohantyHuman development report 2007/2008: fighting climate change: human solidarity in a divided world. SummaryHuman develpment reports 2007/2008: fighting climate change: human solidarity in a divided worldSocial Exclusion and Social Solidarity: Three ParadigmsFighting climate change : human solidarity in a divided world : climate changeIntergenerational Solidarity in Aging Families: An Example of Formal Theory Construction

同义词unity

consolidation 同根词solidly

solidifying

solidify

solidified

solidification

solid s开头的单词Systems Operator

systems analysis

Systems Engineer

Systemic Scleroderma

Systemic Lupus Erythematous

Systems Adviser

systemic thinking

systemic lupus erythematosus

systematic approach

Systematic Risk

systematic training model

system structure 词汇所属分类Billions 亿万_财富之战 Season1&2

《绝望的主妇》(Desperate Housewives) 全八季词频大全

英语单词词频20000之1-6000

《席德梅尔的文明》

英文新闻阅读词汇

美国当代语料库(COCA) 6000-8000词 字母词汇表更多i开头的单词Izzie

izzat

izzard

Ize

izba

izard

r开头的单词ryukyuan

ryukyu

RYS

ryot

rynd

ryke

t开头的单词tea table

tzitzis

tzimmes

tzigane

Tzetzes

tzetze 分类词汇表更多建筑行业wiring

wire cutters

wire cutter

window

wheelbarrow

welder

汽车行业wrecker

wiring

wing mirror

wing

windscreen wiper

windscreen

食品行业yellow wine

wu chia pee

white wine

whisky

vodka

vinegar 人名姓氏表更多男zack

zachary

Zachariah

young

York

Yates

女Zola

Zoe

Zenobia

Zenia

Zena

Zandra

男/女Yong

wynn

winter

willie

Whitney

wally 新东方柯林斯词典 托福考试练习 雅思预测2024年雅思考试重点题汇总[听力|阅读|写作|口语]

2024年2月雅思考试听力|阅读|写作|口语重点题汇总

2024年1月雅思考前必刷题听力|阅读|口语|写作汇总

2024年3月雅思考试听力|阅读|写作|口语重点题汇总

[雅思考前必刷]2024年1月雅思口语考前必刷题Part 2&3地点类

2020年9月雅思口语新题part1:shopping

2021年1月雅思口语新题part2:你认为可以教别人的技能

[雅思考前必刷]2024年1月雅思口语考前必刷题Part 2&3事件类

2020年9月雅思口语新题part1:Activity

2021年1月雅思口语新题part2:你以前看过的现场体育赛事

关于我们

商务合作

广告服务

代理商区域

客服中心

在线留言

合作伙伴

人员招聘

联系我们

网站地图

© 2000-2024 koolearn.com 版权所有    全国客服专线:400-676-2300

京ICP证050421号 京ICP备05067669号-2  京公安备110-1081940  网络视听许可证0110531号

新东方教育科技集团旗下成员公司

solidarity - WordReference.com 英汉词典

solidarity - WordReference.com 英汉词典

WordReference.com | 在线语言字典

英汉词典

| solidarity

×

英语-中文

中文-英语

英语-西班牙语

西班牙语-英语

英语-意大利语

意大利语-英语

英语-法语

法语-英语

English definition

英语同义词

西班牙语-法语

法语-西班牙语

西班牙语-葡萄牙语

葡萄牙语-西班牙语

Español: definición

Español: sinónimos

Català: definició

英语-德语

德语-英语

更多……

论坛

另请参见:

soli

solicit

solicitant

solicitation

soliciting

solicitor

solicitous

solicitude

solid

solid-state

solidarity

solidification

solidify

solidity

solidly

solidus

soliloquize

soliloquy

solipsism

solipsistic

solitaire

热门搜索:

查看全部

solidarity

[links]

Listen:

UK:*UK and possibly other pronunciationsUK and possibly other pronunciations/ˌsɒlɪˈdærəti/US:USA pronunciation: IPA and respellingUSA pronunciation: IPA/ˌsɑlɪˈdærɪti/ ,USA pronunciation: respelling(sol′i dar′i tē)

ⓘ一个或多个论坛线程和你的搜索词完全匹配

定义 |

西班牙语 |

法语 |

英语同义词 |

Conjugator [EN] |

上下文 |

图像

Inflections of 'solidarity' (n): npl: solidarities

WordReference English-Chinese Dictionary © 2024:主要翻译英语中文

solidarity n (unity, mutual support)SCSimplified Chinese 团结一致 tuán jié yí zhì TCTraditional Chinese 團結一致

  SCSimplified Chinese 齐心协力 tuán jié yí zhì,qí xīn xié lì TCTraditional Chinese 同心協力

  SCSimplified Chinese 相互扶持 tuán jié yí zhì,xiāng hù fú chí

 The women's display of solidarity was touching.

 

有所遗漏?报告错误或提出改进建议

WordReference English-Chinese Dictionary © 2024:复合形式:英语中文

in solidarity with prep (as a show of support for)SCSimplified Chinese 声援… shēng yuán TCTraditional Chinese 聲援...

  SCSimplified Chinese 表示支持… shēng yuán,biǎo shì zhī chí

 I'm in solidarity with the workers in their struggle for better conditions.

 

有所遗漏?报告错误或提出改进建议

Collins Chinese Dictionary Plus (3rd edition), 2011:

solidarity [sɔlɪˈdærɪtɪ]

n

[u]

团(團)结(結)一致 tuánjié yīzhì to show solidarity (with sb) 显(顯)示(同某人)站在一起 xiǎnshì (tóng mǒurén) zhàn zài yīqǐ

在这些条目还发现'solidarity':

在英文解释里:

all for one

- be with

- rally around

- sisterhood

- stand next to

- stand shoulder to shoulder with

- stand with

- united front

- unity

标题中含有单词 'solidarity' 的论坛讨论:未在Chinese论坛中找到有关“solidarity”的讨论As much integration as necessary, as much solidarity as possible - English Only forum

develop resilience and solidarity - English Only forum

embrace of solidarity - English Only forum

from any solidarity - English Only forum

human solidarity as compatible - English Only forum

I learned what work for solidarity and fairness means - English Only forum

In Solidarity with or to Show Solidarity with? - English Only forum

masks are an important signal that it’s not business as usual as well as an act of solidarity. - English Only forum

new security relations which excluded the United States and which made Latin American solidarity into ... - English Only forum

playing out solidarity - English Only forum

Show our solidarity - English Only forum

solidarity as a verb - English Only forum

solidarity of proximity - English Only forum

Solidarity speaker - English Only forum

solidarity... - English Only forum

substitute for “solidarity” - English Only forum

Sympathy Vs solidarity - English Only forum

the president of the 10 October Peace and Solidarity Association - English Only forum

to call itself a place of solidarity - English Only forum

to express my solidarity with or to – and alternative formulations - English Only forum

to show solidarity with - (I'm ...... with them) - English Only forum

访问Chinese 论坛。帮助 WordReference: 在论坛上提问。

Go to Preferences page and choose from different actions for taps or mouse clicks.

查看 "solidarity" 的谷歌机器翻译。

其他语言: 西班牙语 | 法语 | 意大利语 | 葡萄牙语 | 罗马尼亚语 | 德语 | 荷兰语 | 瑞典语 | 俄语 | 波兰语 | 捷克语 | 希腊语 | 土耳其语 | 日语 | 韩语 | 阿拉伯语

链接:

⚙️偏好 |

缩略语 |

隐私政策 |

服务条款 |

支持 WR |

论坛 |

建议

广告

广告

报告不适当的广告。

WordReference.com

WORD OF THE DAY

GET THE DAILY EMAIL!

成为WordReference的支持者,浏览网站再也不受广告的打扰。

版权 © 2024 WordReference.com

English version

请报告任何问题。

×